_________________________________________________
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
On the Social Contract
or
Principles of Political Right
_________________________________________________
[This translation by Ian Johnston of Vancouver Island
University, Nanaimo, BC, Canada, first posted online in 2014, has certain copyright
restrictions. For details please consult the following link Copyright. This
translation is available in the form of a paperback book from Richer Resources Publications.
Copies of this translation in the form of a Word file formatted as a booklet
suitable for printing and distributing to students are available free of
charge. Please contact Ian Johnston.]
Translator’s Note
This translation is
based upon the 1762 French edition of Du contrat social. Additions to that text in a later
edition (1782) are given in the endnotes.
A link to an
endnote is indicated by a superscript number. The superscript numbers with the
letter R beside them (e.g., 24R) indicate a link to a note from Rousseau’s text; those numbers without a
letter beside them (e.g., 24) indicate a link to an endnote provided by the translator.
The quotations in
languages other than French that Rousseau has inserted into his text have been
translated into English within the text, and the original words have been included
in an endnote.
Table
of Contents
Which examines how people pass
from the state of nature into the civil state and what are the essential conditions
of the pact.
Chapter 1: Subject of this
First Book
Chapter 2:
On the First Societies
Chapter 3:
On the Right of the Strongest
Chapter 4:
On Slavery
Chapter 5:
That It is Always Necessary to Go Back to a First Agreement
Chapter 6:
On the Social Compact
Chapter 7:
On the Sovereign
Chapter 8:
On the Civil State
Chapter 9:
On Real Property
Book 2
Which deals with legislation.
Chapter 1: That Sovereignty
is Inalienable
Chapter 2:
That Sovereignty is Indivisible
Chapter 3:
Whether the General Will Can Be Mistaken
Chapter 4:
On the Limits of Sovereign Power
Chapter 5:
On the Right of Life and Death
Chapter 6:
On the Law
Chapter 7: On
the Legislator
Chapter 8:
On the People
Chapter 9:
On the People (continued)
Chapter 10:
On the People (continued)
Chapter 11:
On the Various Systems of Legislation
Chapter 12:
The Division of the Laws
Book 3
Which deals with political
laws, that is to say, with the form
of the government.
Chapter 1: On Government in
General
Chapter 2:
On the Principle that Determines the Various Forms of
Government
Chapter 3:
Division of Governments
Chapter 4:
On Democracy
Chapter 5:
On Aristocracy
Chapter 6:
On Monarchy
Chapter 7:
On Mixed Governments
Chapter 8:
That Not All Forms of Government are Appropriate for Every Country
Chapter 9:
On the Signs of a Good Government
Chapter 10:
On the Abuse of Government and Its Tendency to
Degenerate
Chapter 11:
On the Death of the Body Politic
Chapter 12:
How Sovereign Authority Is Maintained
Chapter 13:
How Sovereign Authority Is Maintained (continued)
Chapter 14:
How Sovereign Authority Is Maintained (continued)
Chapter 15:
On Deputies or Representatives
Chapter 16:
That the Institution of Government is not a Contract.
Chapter 17:
On the Institution of Government
Chapter 18:
Ways to Prevent Usurpations of the Government
Book 4
Which continues to deal with political
laws and sets out ways
one can strengthen the constitution of the state.
Chapter 1: That the General
Will is Indestructible
Chapter 2:
On Voting
Chapter 3:
On Elections
Chapter 4:
On the Roman Comitia
Chapter 5:
On the Tribunate
Chapter 6:
On Dictatorship
Chapter 7:
On the Censorship
Chapter 8:
On Civil Religion
Chapter 9:
Conclusion
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
On the Social Contract
This small treatise
is part of a more extensive work that I carried out earlier, without having
taken into account my own strength, and that I abandoned a long time ago. Of
the various parts one could extract from what was completed then, this is the
most significant, and to me it seemed the least unworthy of being offered to
the public. The rest no longer exists.
I wish to explore
whether in the civil order, if one takes men as they are and laws as they might
be, there can be some sure and legitimate rule of administration. In this investigation,
I will attempt always to unite what right permits with what interest prescribes,
so that there will no separation of justice and utility.
I launch my
undertaking without demonstrating the importance of my subject. People will ask
me if I am writing on politics as a prince or a legislator. My answer is that I
am neither, and that is the reason I am writing on politics. If I were a prince
or a legislator, I would not waste my time talking about what must be done. I
would do it, or else keep quiet.
Since I was born a
citizen of a free state and a member of the sovereignty, no matter how weak the
influence of my voice on public affairs may be, the right to vote on such issues
is enough to impose on me the duty to study them. And every time I meditate on
governments, I am happy that in my research I always discover new reasons to
love the government of my country!
Chapter 1
Subject of This First Book
Man was born free, and
everywhere he is in chains. Someone who believes he is the master of others
does not escape being more enslaved than they are. How did this transformation
come about? I do not know. What can render it legitimate? This question I believe
I can resolve.
If I were to
consider nothing but power and the effects which follow from it, I would say
this: as long as a people is compelled to obey and does obey, it is doing well;
as soon as it can throw off its yoke and does shake it off, it is doing even
better, for by recovering its liberty through the same right which robbed the
people of it, either it is justified in taking it back or those who deprived
the populace of freedom had no justification for doing so. But the social order
is a sacred right that serves as the foundation for all the others. This right,
however, does not come from nature and is thus founded on conventions. It is a
matter of knowing what these conventions are. However, before coming to that, I
ought to establish the validity of what I have just asserted.
Chapter 2
On the First Societies
The oldest of all
societies and the only natural one is that of the family. And even there, the
children remain linked to the father only as long as they need him for their
self-preservation. As soon as this need ends, the natural bond dissolves. Once
the children are free of the obedience they owed their father and the father is
free of the care he owed his children, they all return equally to independence.
If they continue to remain united, this is no longer natural but voluntary, and
the family maintains itself merely by convention.
This common liberty
is a consequence of the nature of man. His first law is to look after his own
preservation, his first cares are those he owes himself, and as soon as he reaches
the age of reason, since he is the sole judge of the means appropriate to preserving
himself, he thereby becomes his own master.
Thus, the family
is, if you will, the first model of political societies. The leader is viewed
as the father, and the people as the children. Since they are all born equal
and free, they do not alienate their freedom except for practical convenience.
The only difference is that in the family the love of the father for his children
repays him for the care he takes of them and that in the state the pleasure of
commanding replaces this love, which the leader does not feel for his people.
Grotius denies that
all human power is established for the benefit of those who are governed. He
cites slavery as an example. His most characteristic style of reasoning
is always to establish right by an appeal to fact.1R One could use a
more logical method, but not one more favourable to tyrants.
Thus, according to
Grotius, it is unclear whether the human race belongs to a hundred men or
whether these hundred men belong to the human race, and in his whole work he
seems to incline to the former opinion. That is what Hobbes’ maintains, as
well. And so, from their perspective, the human race is divided into herds of
cattle, each of which has its chief, who guards it in order to
devour it.2
Just as a shepherd
has a nature superior to that of his flock, so the shepherds of men, who are
their leaders, also possess a nature superior to that of their peoples. The emperor
Caligula, according to what Philo reports, followed similar reasoning and from
this analogy came to the appropriate conclusion that either
kings were gods or the people were beasts.3
Caligula’s
reasoning is the same as the arguments in Hobbes and Grotius. Before all of
them, Aristotle had also claimed that men are not naturally equal but that some
are born for slavery and others for dominion.
Aristotle was
correct, but he took the effect for the cause. All men born into slavery are
born for slavery. Nothing is more certain. Slaves lose everything in their
chains, even the desire to escape them. They love their servitude,
just as Ulysses’ companions loved their brutish condition.4R So,
then, if there are slaves by nature, that is because there have been slaves
against nature. Force created the first slaves; their cowardice has kept them
in that condition.
I have not said
anything about king Adam or emperor Noah, father of three great monarchs who divided
up the universe among them, as did the children of Saturn, whom some have
claimed they recognize in Noah’s sons. I hope that people will find my moderation
agreeable, for since I am a direct descendant of one of these princes—perhaps
of the oldest branch—how do I know that with a verification of title I might
not find myself the legitimate king of the human race? Whatever the case, one
cannot deny that Adam was the sovereign of the world, just as Robinson Crusoe
was of his island, as long as he was the sole inhabitant. This empire had the
advantage that in it the monarch was secure on his throne and
had no fear of rebellions, wars, or conspirators.5
Chapter 3
On the Right of the Strongest
The strongest is
never strong enough to be master all the time, unless he transforms his power
into right and obedience into duty. From that emerges the right of the
strongest, a right which, although apparently intended ironically, has been
established as a genuine principle. But are we never to receive an explanation
of this phrase? Force is physical power. I do not see what morality can result
from its effects. To yield to force is an act of necessity, not of will, at
most an act of prudence. In what sense can that be a duty?
Let us assume for a
moment that this alleged right exists. I maintain that the result of such a
right is nothing but inexplicable nonsense. For as soon as it is force which creates
right, the effect changes with the cause. Every force that is more powerful
than the first succeeds to its right. Once we can disobey with impunity, we can
do so legitimately, and since the strongest is always right, it is simply a
matter of acting in a way that makes us the strongest. But what kind of right
perishes when force ends? If we must obey because of force, we have no need to
obey because it is our duty, and if we are no longer forced to obey, we have no
obligation to do so. One can see, therefore, that this word right adds nothing to force. In this context, it signifies
nothing at all.
Obey those with
power. If that means yield to force, it is a good precept, but superfluous. I
reply that it will never be violated. All power comes from God—that I
concede—but all sickness comes from Him as well. Does that mean we are forbidden
to summon the doctor? If a brigand surprises me in a part of the forest, am I
not merely compelled by force to surrender my purse, but also in conscience
obliged to give it to him, when I could withhold it? For the pistol he holds
is, in the end, also a power.
So let us
acknowledge that force does not create right and that we are obliged to obey
only legitimate powers. Thus, we come back to my original question.
Since no man has a
natural authority over his fellow man and since force creates no rights,
therefore conventions remain as the basis of all legitimate authority among human
beings.
If a particular
individual can alienate his liberty, Grotius says, and make
himself the slave of a master, why could not an entire people alienate its
liberty and make itself subject to a king? In this question there are a number
of ambiguous words which require an explanation, but let us restrict ourselves
to that word alienate. To alienate
means to give or to sell. Now, a man who makes himself the slave of someone
else is not giving but selling himself, at least for his subsistence. But why does a people sell itself? For a king, far from providing
his subjects their subsistence, derives his own only from them, and,
according to Rabelais, a king does not live on a pittance.6 So do the subjects surrender their persons on
condition that their goods will also be taken away? I do not see what they have
left to preserve.
Someone will say
that the despot assures his subjects civil tranquillity. That may be so, but
what do they gain from that, if the wars which his ambition draws them into, if
his insatiable greed and the humiliating demands of his ministers bring them
more grief than their own quarrels would have done? What do they gain from it,
if this tranquillity itself is one of their miseries? People also live
peacefully in dungeons. Is that enough to make them a good place to live? The
Greeks imprisoned in the Cyclops’ cave lived there peacefully,
while waiting for their turn to be eaten.7
To say that a man
surrenders himself gratuitously is to make an absurd and inconceivable claim.
Such an act is illegitimate and void, for the sole reason that the man who does
this is not in his right mind. To say the same thing about an entire people is
to assume a population of madmen. Madness creates no rights.
Even if each man
were able to alienate himself, he cannot alienate his children. They are born human
beings and free. Their liberty belongs to them. They are the only one who have the right to dispose of it. No one else has that right.
Before they reach the age of reason, the father can stipulate in their name the
conditions for their preservation, for their wellbeing, but he cannot give them
away irrevocably and unconditionally. For such a gift is contrary to the purposes
of nature and goes beyond the rights of paternity. Thus, for an arbitrary
government to be legitimate, in every generation the people would have to have
the power to accept or reject it. But then this government would no longer be
arbitrary.
To renounce one’s
liberty is to renounce one’s quality as a man, the rights of humanity, and even
its duties. There is no possible compensation for someone who surrenders everything.
Such a renunciation is incompatible with the nature of man, and to remove all
liberty from someone’s will is to remove all morality from his actions.
Finally, it is an empty and contradictory convention to stipulate, on the one
hand, an absolute authority and, on the other, an unlimited obedience. Is it
not clear that we have no obligations towards someone from whom we have the
right to demand everything? And does this condition alone, where there is no
equivalence or exchange, not involve nullifying the act? For what right would
my slave have against me, since all he possesses belongs to me, and, now that
his right is mine, this right I have against myself is a meaningless phrase?
Grotius and others
derive from warfare an alternative origin for the alleged right of slavery.
Since the victor, according to them, has the right to kill the conquered, the
latter can purchase his life back at the expense of his liberty, and this convention
is all the more legitimate because it is profitable to both parties.
But it is clear
that this alleged right to kill the conquered does not in any way result from
the state of war. Given the mere fact that human beings living in their
original independence have no sufficiently constant relations among themselves
to constitute either a state of peace or a state of war, they are not naturally
enemies. What constitutes war is a relationship between things and not between
men, and since a state of war cannot arise from simple personal relationships,
but only from relationships involving property [rélations réelles],
a private war or a war of man against man cannot exist, either in the state of
nature, where there is no constant property, or in the social state, where
everything is under the authority of laws.
Individual combats,
duels, and confrontations are not acts that establish a state, and as far as
concerns private wars, authorized by the ordinances [Établissements] of Louis IX, king of
France, and suspended by the Peace of God, these are abuses of feudal government,
an absurd system if ever there was one, contrary to the
principles of natural right and to all good politics.8
Hence, war is a not
a relation between one man and another, but between one state and another. In
war the individual participants are enemies only by accident, not as men, nor
even as citizens, but as soldiers, not as members of their
homeland, but as its defenders.9 Finally, each
state can have as its enemies only other states and not other men, for between
things with different natures we cannot establish a single authentic relationship.
This principle even
complies with established maxims of all times and with the constant practice of
all civilized peoples. Declarations of war are warnings, not so much to those
in power, as to their subjects. A foreigner—whether king, individual, or
people—who steals, kills, or detains the subjects without declaring war on the
prince is not an enemy but a brigand. Even in open warfare, a just prince in a
hostile country rightly seizes everything which belongs to the public, but he
respects the person and the goods of individual people. He respects the rights
on which his own are founded. Since the object of war is the destruction of the
enemy state, one has a right to kill its defenders as long as they bear arms.
But as soon as they lay down their weapons and surrender, thus ceasing to be
enemies or tools of the enemy, they return to being simply men, and one no
longer has a right to take their lives. Sometimes one can kill a state without
killing a single one of its members. And war grants no right that is not
essential to its purpose. These principles are not those of Grotius, nor are
they founded on the authority of poets. But they are derived from the nature of
things and are based upon reason.
As far as the right
of conquest is concerned, that has no foundation other than the law of the
strongest. If war does not give the victor the right to massacre the conquered
people, this right which he does not have cannot be the basis of his right to enslave
them. One has the right to kill an enemy only when one cannot make him a slave.
Hence, the right to make someone a slave does not stem from the right to kill
him. It is thus an iniquitous exchange to make him purchase his life, to which
one has no right, at the price of his liberty. Is it not clear that by establishing
the right of life and death on the right of slavery and the right of slavery on
the right of life and death one is falling into a vicious circle?
And even assuming
this terrible right to kill everyone, I claim that someone enslaved in war or a
conquered people is not bound by anything at all where their master is concerned,
other than to obey him as long as they are forced to do so. By accepting an
equivalent for his life, the victor has not done him a favour, for instead of
killing him without profit, he has killed him for his own use. And thus, it is
far from the case that he has acquired any authority over him that is not linked
to force, and so the state of war continues between them, as before. The very
relationship between them is the effect of war, and using the right of war does
not presuppose any treaty of peace. They have established a convention. That
may well be so. But this convention, far from destroying the state of war,
assumes its continuation.
Thus, however one
examines the issues, the right of slavery is non-existent, not only because it
is illegitimate, but also because it is absurd and signifies nothing. The words
slavery and right are contradictory. They are mutually exclusive. Whether one
man is talking to another or one man is speaking to a people, the following
statement will always be equally absurd: I
am making an agreement with you entirely at your expense and entirely to my advantage,
which I shall observe as long as it
pleases me, and you will observe it as long as it pleases me.
Chapter 5
That It is Always Necessary to Go Back to a First
Agreement
Even if I were to
concede everything I have refuted up to this point, those who agitate in favour
of despotism would not have advanced their cause any further. There will always
be a great difference between subduing a multitude and ruling a society. If scattered
individuals were successively enslaved to one man I still see nothing there, no
matter how many there might be, but a master and slaves. I do not see a people
and its leader. It is, if you will, an aggregation, but not an association.
There is in it no public good and no body politic. Even if that man had enslaved
half the world, he is still merely an individual man. His interest, separate
from the interest of the others, is always merely a private interest. If this
same man happens to die, after he is gone his empire remains scattered and
disconnected, just as an oak tree, once fire has consumed it, collapses and dissolves
into a heap of ashes.
A people, Grotius
says, can give itself to a king. According to him, therefore, a people is a people before it gives itself to a king. This
gift is itself a civil act. It assumes a public deliberation. Hence, before
examining the act by which a people chooses a king, it would be good to examine
the act by which a people becomes a people. For since this latter act is
necessarily prior to the former, it is the true foundation of the society.
In fact, if there
were no previous agreement, unless the election of a king was unanimous, where
would there be an obligation on the minority to submit to the choice of the majority?
Where would the hundred people who desire a master acquire the right to vote on
behalf of the ten who do not? The law of decisions by majority vote is itself established
by convention and presupposes unanimity on at least one occasion.
Chapter 6
On the Social Compact
I assume that, once
men have reached the stage where the obstacles harmful to their preservation in
a state of nature are winning out, because these obstacles resist the forces
which each individual can employ in order to maintain himself in this
condition, at that point this primitive condition can no longer continue, and
the human race would die out if it did not change its way of life.
Now, since men are
incapable of creating new forces but only of uniting and directing existing ones,
they have no way of preserving themselves other than to form by aggregation a
sum of their forces, something that could prevail over that resistance, then to
bring these forces to bear by a single mobile power, and to make them work in
concert.
This sum of forces
cannot arise except through several people combining together. But since the
power and liberty of each man are the principal instruments of his preservation,
how will he commit them without harming himself and without neglecting the care
he owes himself? If we apply this difficulty to my subject, we can define it in
the following terms:
“To find a form of
association which defends and protects with full communal force the person and
the possessions of each member and in which each person, by uniting with all,
nevertheless obeys only himself and remains as free as
before.”
Such is the
fundamental problem to which the social contract provides the solution.
The clauses of this
contract are determined by the nature of the act in such a way that the least
modification would render them empty and ineffectual. As a result, even though
they perhaps have never been formally stated, they are the same everywhere and
are tacitly admitted and recognized everywhere, until the moment when, once the
social pact has been violated, each person then returns to his original rights
and resumes his natural liberty, losing the conventional freedom for which he
renounced it.
These clauses,
properly understood, all come down to one, that is, the total alienation of
each member of the association, along with all his rights, to the entire
community. For, first of all, since each person gives himself entirely, the
condition is equal for all, and since the condition is the same for everyone,
no one has an interest in making it burdensome for the others.
In addition,
because the alienation is made without reservation, the union is as perfect as
it can be, and no member of the association has any further demands. For, given
that there would not be any shared superior who could decide between particular
members and the public, if individuals were to retain certain rights, each one
would, on some point, be his own judge and would soon claim to be that in all
things. The state of nature would thus remain, and the association would necessarily
become tyrannical or pointless.
Finally, since each
person gives himself to everyone, he gives himself to no one, and since there
is no member of the association over whom he does not acquire the same right which
he grants that person over himself, he gains the equivalent of everything he
loses, as well as more power to preserve what he has.
If, then, we remove
from the social pact what is not part of its essence, we will find that it is
reduced to the following terms: Each one
of us puts his person and all his power in common under the supreme direction
of the general will, and as a body we receive each member as an indivisible
part of the totality.
This act of
association immediately replaces the individual personality of each member of
the contract with a moral and collective body composed of as many members as
there are voices in the assembly. And from this same act, the assembly acquires
its unity, its communal self, its
life, and its will. The public person produced in this way by the union of all
the others in earlier days took the name of city and now bears the name of republic or body politic.10R It
is called the state by its members
when it is passive, the sovereign
when it is active, and a power when
it is being compared to others like itself. So far as the members of the
association are concerned, they take on collectively the name of a people, calling themselves, as individuals,
citizens, since they are participants
in the sovereign authority, and subjects,
since they submit to the laws of the state. These terms, however, are often
confused and taken for one another. It is sufficient to know how to distinguish
them when they are used with complete precision.
We see in this
formulation that the act of association contains a reciprocal commitment
between the public and the individuals, and that, by making a contract with
himself, so to speak, each individual finds himself bound in a double relationship:
that is, as a member of the sovereign with each individual, and, as a member of
the state, with the sovereign. However, we cannot apply here that principle of
civil right which states that no person is bound by commitments made to himself, for there is a significant difference between having
an obligation to oneself and having an obligation to a totality of which one is
a part.
We must also
observe that public deliberations which can impose obligations on all subjects
to the sovereign, given the two different relationships under which each citizen-subject
is regarded, cannot, for the opposite reason, impose obligations on the sovereign
to itself and thus that it is contrary to the nature of the body politic for
the sovereign to impose a law on itself which it cannot break. Since the
sovereign can view itself in terms of only one single relationship, it is then
in the position of a particular individual making a contract with himself. From
that we see that there is not and cannot be any sort of fundamental law imposing
obligations on the body of the people, not even the social contract. That does
not mean that this body cannot properly enter into undertakings with others concerning
matters which do not violate this contract, for as far as foreigners are concerned,
the body politic becomes a single entity, an individual.
But since the body
politic or the sovereign derives its being only from the sanctity of the
contract, it can never commit itself, even towards foreigners, to anything
which goes against this original act, for instance, by alienating some part of
itself or by submitting itself to another sovereign. To violate the act by
which it exists would be to annihilate itself, and what is nothing creates
nothing.
As soon as this
multitude is thus unified into a body, one cannot offend against one of its
members without attacking the body itself; and it is even more difficult to
harm the body without its members feeling the effects. Thus, obligation and
interest require the two contracting parties equally to provide help to one another,
and in this double relationship the same people should seek to combine all the
advantages which depend on it.
Now, since the
sovereign is composed only of individuals who make it up, it does not have and
cannot have an interest contrary to theirs. Therefore, the sovereign power has
no need to give its subjects a guarantee, because it is impossible that the
body would want to harm all its members, and later on we shall see that it
cannot harm any particular individual. From the very fact that it exists, the
sovereign is always everything it ought to be.
That, however, is
not the same for the subjects with regard to the sovereign, since, despite
their common interest, the sovereign would have no guarantee of their commitments
unless it found ways of assuring itself of their loyalty.
In fact, each
individual, as a man, can have a particular will at odds with or different from
the general will which he has as a citizen. His particular interest can speak
to him in an entirely different way from the common interest. His absolute and
naturally independent existence can lead him to look on what he owes the common
cause as a gratuitous contribution, the loss of which will be less injurious to
others than the payment is onerous to him, and by viewing the moral person who
constitutes the state as simply a rational entity, because he is not a man, he
may wish to enjoy the rights of a citizen without being willing to fulfil the
duties of a subject, an injustice whose progress would lead to
the ruin of the body politic.11
Therefore, to
ensure that the social pact is not an empty formula, it tacitly includes this
commitment, which alone can give force to the others: whoever refuses to obey
the general will shall be compelled to do so by the entire body. This simply
means that he will be forced to be free. For that is the condition which, by
giving each citizen to his native land, protects him from all personal dependency,
a condition which creates the subtle working of the political machine and which
alone confers legitimacy on civil commitments, which without it would be absurd,
tyrannical, and subject to the most enormous abuses.
This transition
from the state of nature to the civil state produces in man an extremely remarkable
change, by substituting justice for instinct in his conduct and by giving his actions
a moral quality they previously lacked. Only then, when the voice of duty takes
over from physical impulses and when right takes the place of appetite, does
man, who up to that point has considered nothing apart from himself, see
himself compelled to act on other principles and to consult his reason before
listening to his inclinations. Although in this state he deprives himself of
several of the advantages he derives from nature, those he gains in return are
so great: his faculties are stimulated and developed, his ideas grow more
extensive, his feelings are ennobled, and his whole soul is uplifted, so much
so that, if the abuses of this new condition did not often degrade him below
the condition he left, he ought never to stop blessing the happy moment that
tore him away from there forever and that changed him from a stupid and limited
animal into an intelligent being and a man.
Let us reduce this
whole balance sheet to terms we can easily compare. Through the social contract,
man loses his natural liberty and an unlimited right to everything that tempts
him and that he is able to acquire. What he wins is civil liberty and the ownership
of everything he possesses. In order not to be mistaken about these compensations,
we must make a clear distinction between natural
liberty, which has no limits other than the powers of the individual, and civil liberty, which is limited by the
general will, and between possession,
which is merely a result of force or the right of the first occupant, and property, which can be established only
on a positive title.
As well as what has
been mentioned above, we could add to those things a man acquires in the civil
state moral liberty, which alone makes him truly master of himself. For following
the impulses of mere appetite is slavery, while obeying the law which one has
set down for oneself is liberty. However, I have already said too much on this
topic, and the philosophical meaning of the word liberty is not part of my subject here.
Each member of the
community gives himself to it at the moment it is created, just as he truly is,
his person and all his resources, a part of which is the goods he possesses.
This does not mean that possession, through this act of changing hands, changes
its nature and becomes property in the hands of the sovereign. However, since
the forces of the state are incomparably greater than those of an individual,
public possession is also, in fact, stronger and more irrevocable, without
being more legitimate, at least from the point of view of foreigners. For where
its members are concerned, the state is master of all their goods thanks to the
social contract, which within the state serves as the basis for all rights. However,
where other powers are concerned, the state is master only by the right of the
first occupant, which it derives from particular individuals.
Although the right
of the first occupant is more real than the right of the strongest, it does not
become a genuine right until after the establishment of the right of property.
Every man by nature has a right to everything which is necessary to him, but
the positive act which makes him the owner of some goods excludes him from all
the rest. Once his share is determined, he should limit himself to that; he has
no further property right with respect to the community. That is why the right
of the first occupant, which is so weak in the state of nature, is respected by
everyone in civil society. In honouring this right, a person is respecting, not
so much what belongs to other people, as what does not belong to him.
Generally speaking,
in order to authorize the right of first occupant over any territory, the
following conditions must apply: firstly, this territory must not yet be
inhabited by anyone; secondly, one must occupy only as much land as one
requires to subsist; thirdly, one must take possession of the land, not by an
empty ceremony, but by toil and cultivation, the only sign of ownership which,
when legal titles are not available, should be respected by other people.
In fact, by
according the right of first occupant to need and labour, are we not extending
this right as far as it can go? Is it possible to assign this right without
limits? Will it be sufficient to place one’s foot on some common land in order
to claim immediately that one is its master? Will it be sufficient to have the
power to push other men aside for a moment in order to remove from them the
right ever to return there? How can a man or a people seize an immense
territory and take it away from the entire human race other than by a punishable
usurpation, since such an act deprives the rest of humanity of the living space
and the sustenance which nature gives them in common? When Nunez Balboa,
standing on the seashore, took possession of the South Sea and all of South
America in the name of the crown of Castille, was
that enough to dispossess all the inhabitants there and to
exclude from the region all the princes of the world?12 If so, it is quite pointless to multiply these
ceremonies, and the Catholic king in his private study merely had to take
possession all at once of the entire universe, provided he later removed from
his empire what other princes have previously made their possessions.
We understand how
the unified and contiguous lands of particular individuals become public territory
and how the right of sovereignty, by extending from the subjects to the land
they occupy, becomes at once real and personal. This process makes those who possess
the land more heavily dependent and turns even their own forces into guarantees
of their fidelity. This advantage does not seem to have been fully realized by
ancient monarchs, who called themselves only kings of the Persians, Scythians,
or Macedonians, apparently considering themselves rulers of men rather than masters
of countries. Today’s rulers are more astute and call themselves kings of
France, Spain, England, and so on. By holding the land like this, they are
quite confident of holding its inhabitants.
What is remarkable
about this alienation is that, by taking the goods of individuals, the
community, far from depriving them, merely assures them of legitimate possession,
for it changes usurpation into a genuine right and enjoyment into ownership.
Then, given that the possessors are considered agents of the public good and
that their rights are respected by all the members of the state and maintained
with all their forces against foreigners, these owners, by a transfer advantageous
to the public and even more so to themselves, have, so to speak, acquired everything
which they gave up. This paradox is easily explained by the distinction between
the rights that the sovereign and the owner have over the same resources [fonds], as we
will see later on.
It can also happen
that men begin to unite before they possess anything and then later take over a
territory sufficient for all, which they enjoy in common or which they divide
up among themselves, either equally or according to proportions determined by
the sovereign. However this acquisition is carried out, the right of each
particular individual over his own resources [fonds] is always subordinate to the
right of the community to everything, without which there would be no strength
in the social bond and no real force in the exercise of the sovereignty.
I will end this
chapter and this book with a comment which should serve as the foundation for
the entire social system: instead of destroying natural equality, the
fundamental pact, by contrast, substitutes for the physical inequalities which
nature could have established among men a moral and legitimate equality, and so
people who could be unequal in power or intelligence all become
equal by convention and by right.13R
End of Book 1
Book 2
Chapter 1
That The Sovereignty is Inalienable
The first and most important
consequence of the principles established above is that only the general will
can direct the forces of the state according to the purpose for which it was
set up, that is, for the common good. For if the opposition of particular interests
made the institution of societies necessary, the agreement
among these same interests made it possible. What these different interests
have in common creates the social bond, and if there were not some point on
which all the interests were in agreement, no society could exist. Now, this common
interest is the only basis on which society should be governed.
Therefore, I
maintain that, since the sovereignty is nothing but the exercise of the general
will, it can never be alienated and that the sovereign, which is only a
collective being, cannot be represented except by itself.
The power can be readily transferred, but not the will.
In fact, if it is
not impossible for a particular will to agree on some point with the general
will, it is at least impossible for this agreement to be durable and constant,
for the particular will tends by its nature towards things it prefers, and the
general will tends towards equality. It is even more impossible to have a
guarantee of this agreement, even if it should always exist. That would be a
result, not of art, but of chance. The sovereign may well say, “I actually will
what such and such a man wills or at least what he says he wills,” but it
cannot say, “What this man is going to will tomorrow, I shall will, as well,”
because it is absurd that the will gives itself
fetters for the future and because no will is required to consent to anything
contrary to the good of the entity doing the willing. So if a
people promises simply to obey, by that act it is dissolving itself and
losing its quality as a people. The instant there is a master, there is no
longer a sovereign, and from that point on the body politic is destroyed.
This is not to say
that orders from the leaders cannot pass for expressions of the general will,
so long as the sovereign is free to oppose them and does not do so. In such a
case, one should assume that universal silence indicates the consent of the people.
This point will be explained in greater detail.
Chapter 2
That the Sovereignty is Indivisible
For the same reason
that the sovereignty is inalienable, it is also indivisible.
For either the will is general, or it is not.14R It
is the will of the body of the people or of merely a part. In the first case,
this will, once declared, is an act of sovereignty and creates law. In the
second case, it is only a particular will or an act of magistracy, at most a decree.
But our political
thinkers, unable to divide sovereignty in principle, divide it according to its
aims—separating it into force and will, into legislative power and executive
power, into rights of taxation, of justice and war, into internal administration
and the power to deal with foreigners. Sometimes they mix all these parts
together, and sometimes they separate them. They turn the sovereign into a
fantastic entity made up of different pieces. It is as if they were producing a
man from several bodies, one of which had eyes, another arms, another feet, and
nothing else. People say that Japanese conjurors dismember a child in full view
of the spectators, then throw all its limbs into the air, one after the other,
and make the child fall down again, alive and completely reassembled. The conjuring
tricks of our political thinkers are almost like that: after they have dismembered
the social body using an illusion worthy of a fair, they put the pieces back together
again—no one knows how.
This error arises
because they have not established precise notions about sovereign authority and
because they have taken for parts of this authority things that were merely emanations
from it. Thus, for example, they have looked upon the acts of declaring war and
of making peace as acts of sovereignty, which they are not, for each of these
actions is not a law but simply an application of the law, a particular act
which determines how the law applies to a case, as we shall see clearly once
the idea attached to the word law has
been defined.
By exploring the
other divisions in the same manner, we would find that every time we think we
see the sovereignty split up, we are mistaken and that the rights which we take
for parts of this sovereignty are all subordinate to it and always assume supreme
wills whose execution these rights merely authorize.
It would be
impossible to state how much obscurity this lack of precision has cast over the
decisions of those who have written about issues of political rights, when, by
applying the principles they have established, they wished to judge the
respective rights of kings and peoples. Everyone can see in Chapters 3 and 4 of
the first book of Grotius how this learned man and his translator, Barbeyrac, get tangled up in and confused by their own
sophistries, for fear of saying too much or of not saying enough about something
from their point of view and of offending the interests they had to accommodate.
Grotius, unhappy with his homeland, was a refugee in France and wished to pay
court to Louis XIII, to whom his book was dedicated. He spares no effort to rob
the people of all their rights and to invest kings with them by every possible
artifice. This would have also been much to Barbeyrac’s
taste; he dedicated his translation to the king of England, George I. Unfortunately,
however, the expulsion of James II, which he calls an abdication, forced him to
restrain himself, to distort, and to evade the issue, so as not
to make William a usurper.15 If these two
writers had adopted genuine principles, all the difficulties would have been removed
and they would have always been consistent. But then they would have spoken the
truth, unfortunately for them, and paid court only to the people. For truth
does not lead to fortune, and the populace does not award ambassadorships, or
university chairs, or pensions.
Chapter 3
Whether the General Will Can Be Mistaken
From what has been
said above it follows that the general will is always right and always tends
towards what is useful for the public. However, it does not follow that the
deliberations of the people are always equally correct. We always will our own
good, but we do not always recognize what that is. A people is never corrupted,
but it is often misled, and those are the only times it appears to will what is
bad.
There is often a
significant difference between the will of everyone and the general will. The
latter considers only the common interest; the former considers private
interest and is merely a sum of particular wills. But remove from these same
wills the pluses and minuses which cancel each other out, and
what remains as the sum of the differences is the general will.16R
If, when the
populace has been sufficiently informed and has deliberated, the citizens had
no communication among themselves, the general will would always result from the
large number of small differences, and the decision would always be good. But
when intrigues are launched, partial associations at the expense of the large
one, the will of each of these associations becomes general with respect to its
members and particular with respect to the state. At that point one could say
that there are no longer as many voters as there are men but only as many as
there are associations. The differences become less numerous and provide a less
general result. Finally, when one of these associations is so great that it
wins out over all the others, you no longer have a result which is the sum of
small differences, but a single difference. Then there is no longer a general
will, and the view which prevails is only a particular opinion.
Therefore, in order
to have a clear statement of the general will, it is important that there is no
partial society within the state and that each citizen express only his own
opinion. Such was the unique and sublime system established by the great Lycurgus.
However, if there are partial societies, it is necessary to multiply their
number and prevent them from becoming unequal, something achieved by Solon, Numa, and Servius. These precautions are the only good ways to ensure
that the general will is always enlightened and that the
populace does not make mistakes.17R
Chapter 4
On the Limits of the Sovereign Power
If the state or the
city is simply a moral person whose life consists of the union of its members
and if the most important of its concerns is taking care of its own preservation,
it requires a universal and compelling force to move and arrange each part in
the manner most advantageous to the totality. Just as nature gives each man an
absolute power over all his limbs, the social pact gives the body politic an
absolute power over all its members, and it is this same power that, directed
by the general will, bears, as I have said, the name of sovereignty.
But apart from the
public person, we have to consider the private persons who make it up and whose
life and liberty are naturally independent of it. Therefore, there is a need to
distinguish clearly between the respective rights of the citizens and of the
sovereign and between the obligations which the former have to
carry out as subjects and the natural rights they should enjoy as men.18R
I concede that in
the social pact each man alienates only as much of his power, goods, and
liberty as it is important for the community to have at its disposal, but one
must also concede that the sovereign is the sole judge of what is important.
All the services
which a citizen can render the state, he has an obligation to provide to it as
soon as the sovereign asks for them. But the sovereign, for its part, cannot impose
on the subjects any chains which are useless to the community. It cannot even
will to do so, for according to the law of reason, nothing takes place without
a cause, any more than it does under the law of nature.
The commitments
which bind us to the social body are obligatory only because they are mutual,
and their nature is such that in fulfilling them one cannot work for another
person without working for oneself, as well. Why is the general will always
right, and why does everyone constantly will the wellbeing of each of them, if
not because there is no one who does not apply that word each to himself and who does not think of himself as he votes for
them all? This demonstrates that the equality of right and the concept of
justice it produces stem from the preference each person has for himself and
thus from the nature of man; that for the general will to be truly general it
must be so in its aims as well as in its essence; that it must originate from
all in order to be applied to all; and that it loses its natural rectitude when
it tends towards some individual and determinate purpose, because then, when we
are rendering judgment on something foreign to us, we have no true principle of
equity to guide us.
Indeed, as soon as
it is a question of a fact or of a particular right
in a matter which has not been regulated by a previous general agreement, the issue
becomes contentious. It is a case in which the particular interests are one of
the parties and the public the other, but where I do not see either the law
which must be followed or the judge who should rule on the matter. In such a
case, it would be ridiculous to wish to refer the question to an express
decision of the general will, which can only be the conclusion of one of the
parties and which, for the other party, is therefore merely a particular and
alien will, one tending on this occasion to injustice and subject to error. And
so, just as a particular will cannot represent the general will, the general
will, in its turn, changes its nature when it has a particular object and,
since it is general, cannot pronounce either on a man or on a fact. For
example, when the people of Athens appointed or demoted its leaders, proclaimed
honours for one, imposed penalties on another, and with a multitude of particular
decrees carried out indiscriminately all the actions of government, at that
time the populace no longer had a general will, in the strict sense, for it was
no longer acting as a sovereign but as a magistrate. This will appear contrary
to commonly held ideas, but I must be given time to set down my own.
From this one
should realize that what makes the will general is not so much the number of
votes as the common interest which unites them. For in this system each person
necessarily submits himself to the conditions he imposes on the others, an
admirable agreement between interest and justice, which gives to the common
deliberations an equitable character, which disappears in a discussion of any
particular issue, given the lack of a common interest that unites and
identifies the ruling of the judge with that of the party.
From whatever side
we return to this principle, we always reach the same conclusion, namely, that
the social pact establishes among the citizens such equality that they all commit
themselves to the same conditions and should all enjoy the same rights. Thus,
by the nature of the pact, each act of sovereignty, that is to say, every
authentic act of the general will imposes obligations on or favours all the
citizens equally. Hence, the sovereign recognizes only the body of the nation
and makes no distinctions among any of those who make it up. What, then,
strictly speaking, is an act of sovereignty? It is not an agreement between a superior
and an inferior, but an agreement between a body and each one of its members.
It is a legitimate agreement, because it is founded on the social contract, equitable,
because it is common to all, useful, because it cannot have any purpose other
than the general good, and firm, because it is guaranteed by public force and
the supreme power. As long as the subjects are bound solely to agreements like
this, they are not obeying anyone other than their own will. And to ask how far
the respective rights of the sovereign and of the citizens extend is to ask how
far the latter can commit themselves to themselves, each person to all and all
to each.
We see from this
that the sovereign power, wholly absolute, wholly sacred, and wholly inviolable
as it is, does not and cannot exceed the limits of general agreements and that
every man is fully capable of disposing of what these agreements have left him
of his goods and his liberty, so that the sovereign never has the right to
impose more on one subject than on another, because then, when the issue
becomes particular, the sovereign’s power is no longer competent.
Once we have acknowledged
these distinctions, it is wrong to claim that in the social contract there is
any genuine renunciation on the part of individuals, so much so that their situation,
as a result of this contract, is actually preferable to what it was previously
and that, rather than an alienation, they have only made an advantageous exchange
of an uncertain and precarious way of life for a better and more secure alternative,
trading natural independence for liberty, the power to harm others for their
own security, and their own strength, which others can overwhelm, for a right
which the social union makes invincible. Their very lives, which they have
dedicated to the state, is constantly protected by it, and when they risk their
lives in its defence what are they doing then other than giving back to the
state what they have received from it? What are they doing that they would not
be doing more frequently and more dangerously in the state of nature, when they
would be fighting inevitable battles and putting their lives in peril to defend
what served to preserve them? Everyone has to fight when the homeland needs
him—that is true. But it is also true that no one ever has to fight for himself.
Where our security is concerned, do we not still gain by running some of the
risks we would have to run on our own as soon as that security was taken away
from us?
Chapter 5
On the Right of Life and Death
Since individuals
have no right to take their own lives, one might well ask how they can transfer
this same right, which they do not possess, to the sovereign. This question appears
difficult to resolve only because it is poorly framed. Each man has the right
to risk his own life in order to preserve it. Has anyone ever claimed that a
person who throws himself out of a window to escape a fire is guilty of
suicide? Has this same criminal charge ever been laid against someone who
perishes in a storm at sea, on the ground that when he embarked he was not
ignorant of the danger?
The purpose of the
social treaty is the preservation of those making the contract. A person who
wills this goal also wills the means, and these means are inseparable from certain
risks, even some losses. Someone who wishes to preserve his life at the expense
of others should also give his life for them when the need arises. Now, the
citizen is no longer the judge of the peril which the law wishes him to face,
and when the prince has said to him, “It is in the state’s interest that you
die,” he ought to die, for it is only on that condition that he has lived in
security up to that point, and his life is no longer merely a bountiful gift of
nature but also a conditional gift of the state.
The death penalty
imposed on criminals can be viewed more or less in the same way: in order not
to be the victim of an assassin, we agree to die if we become one. In this
social treaty, far from disposing of his life, a person thinks only of protecting
it, and we should not assume that any of those agreeing to the contract is
intending at the time to get himself hanged.
Furthermore, every
wrongdoer, by attacking social right, becomes, as a result of his crimes, a
rebel and a traitor to his homeland. He ceases to be a member of it by violating
its laws; he even wages war against it. At that point, the preservation of the
state is incompatible with his own. One of the two has
to perish. And when we put the guilty person to death, he is not so much a
citizen as an enemy. The trial and the sentence are the proof and the declaration
that he has broken the social treaty and is thus not a member of the state.
Now, since he has acknowledged that that is what he was, at least by living
there, he should be removed from it by exile, as someone who has violated the
social treaty, or by death, as a public enemy. For an enemy like him is not a moral person. He is a merely a man, and in such
a case it is a right of war to kill the vanquished.
But, someone will
say, condemning a criminal is a particular act. I grant that. But this condemnation
is also not a function of the sovereign. It is a right which the sovereign can
confer without the power to exercise it on its own. All my ideas are consistent,
but I cannot set them down all at once.
We should add that
the frequency of harsh punishment is always a sign of weakness or laziness in
the government. There is no wrongdoer who could not be made good for something.
We have no right to put anyone to death, even as an example, other than a person
whom we cannot preserve without danger.
As far as the right
to pardon is concerned or to exempt a guilty person from the punishment imposed
by the law and pronounced by the judge, it belongs only to the one who is above
the judge and the law, that is to say, to the sovereign, although its right in
this matter is not at all clear, and the cases where it is used are extremely
rare. In a well-governed state, there are few punishments, not because it
issues plenty of pardons, but because there are few criminals. When the state
is growing weak, the multitude of crimes is a guarantee of impunity. Under the
Roman Republic, neither the Senate nor the consuls ever tried to grant pardons.
Even the people did not do so, although it sometimes revoked it own judgments.
Frequent pardons declare that soon criminal acts will no longer need them, and
everyone sees where that leads. But I feel my heart murmuring and restraining
my pen. Let us leave the discussion of these questions to the jukst man who has not done wrong and who has never himself
had need of a pardon.
With the social
pact we have provided existence and life to the body politic. It is now a
matter of giving it, through legislation, movement and will. For the original
act by which this body is formed and united still does not establish any of
those things that need to be done to preserve it.
What is good and
conforms to order is so by the nature of things, independently of human
conventions. All justice comes from God. He alone is its source. But if we knew
how to accept justice from such a lofty place, we would have no need for either
government or laws. Undoubtedly there is a universal justice which
emanates from reason alone, but in order for this justice to be admitted among
us, it must be reciprocal. If we consider things from a human perspective,
because we lack a natural sanction, the laws of justice are ineffectual among
men. All they achieve is the good of the wrongdoer and trouble for the just,
when the latter observes the laws with everyone, but no one observes them with
him. Consequently, we must have conventions and laws to unite rights with
duties and to lead justice back to its object. In the state of nature, where
everything is in common, I do not owe anything to those to whom I have promised
nothing, and I recognize as someone else’s possession only what is of no use to
me. That is not the case in a civil state, where all rights are fixed by law.
But what then, in
the final analysis, is a law? As long as we are content to attach nothing to
this word but metaphysical ideas, we will continue to argue without agreement,
and when we have declared what a law of nature is, we will, for all that, have
no better understanding of what a law of the state is.
I have already
remarked that there is no general will in a matter concerning a particular
object. In effect, this particular object is either within the state or outside
it. If it is outside the state, a will which is alien to the state is not
general in relation it, and if this object is within the state, it is part of
the state. In that case, there is created between the totality and its part a
relation which produces two separate beings: one of them is the part, and the
other is the totality minus this very part. But the totality minus a part is
not a totality, and as long as this relationship continues, there is no longer
a totality but two unequal parts. From this it follows that the will of one is
no longer general with respect to the other.
But when an entire
populace delivers a ruling concerning all the people, it is considering only
itself, and if at that time a relationship is created, it is between the entire
object seen from one point of view and the entire object seen from another
point of view, without any division of the totality. In such a case, the matter
about which the decree is established is general, as is the will which creates
it. This is the act I call a law.
When I say that the
object of the laws is always general, I mean that the law considers the
subjects as a total body and actions in the abstract; it never considers one
man as an individual or a particular action. Hence, the law can readily decree
that there will be privileges, but it cannot confer these on anyone by name;
the law can create several classes of citizens and even designate the qualifications
which give people the right to belong to these classes, but it cannot designate
this or that person for admittance to them; it can establish a monarchical
government and a hereditary succession, but it cannot choose a king or appoint
a royal family. In a word, no function which is linked to an individual object
is part of the legislative power.
With this idea in
mind, we see at once that we no longer need to ask whose role it is to make
laws, since they are acts of the general will, or whether the prince is above
the laws, since he is a member of the state, or whether the law can be unjust,
since no one is unjust to himself, or how we are free and subject to laws,
since they are merely registers of what we have willed.
We also see that
because the law combines the universality of the will with that of the object,
what a man, whoever he may be, orders on his own initiative is not a law. Even
something the sovereign commands concerning a particular object is no closer to
a law, but is a decree. It is an act, not of the sovereignty, but of the magistracy.
Thus, I call every
state ruled by laws, no matter what form its administration may be, a republic.
For only then does the public interest govern and the public entity become something real.19 Every legitimate government is republican.20R I will explain
later what government is.
The laws, strictly
speaking, are only the conditions of the civil association. The people who are subject
to the laws ought to be their author. And ruling on the conditions of society belongs
only to those who have assembled to create it. But how will they regulate these
conditions? Will that be by common agreement, by a sudden inspiration? Does the
body politic have an organ for announcing what it wills? Who will give it the
foresight it requires to formulate its acts and publicize them in advance, or
how will it make them known when the need arises? How would a blind multitude,
which often does not know what it wants, because it rarely knows what is good
for it, carry out all on its own such an enormous and such a difficult
enterprise as a system of legislation? By itself, a people
always desires what is good, but by itself it does not always see what that
is. The general will is always right, but the judgment which guides it is not always
enlightened. It has to be to made to see objects as
they are and sometimes as they ought to appear to it. One needs to show it the
good road it is looking for and to protect it from the seduction of particular
wills. It has to be given a better sense of places and times, to weigh the
attractions of present perceptible advantages against the danger of distant and
hidden evils. Individuals see the good they reject; the public wills the good
it does not see. They are all equally in need of guides. The former must be compelled
to make their wills conform to their reason, and the latter must be taught to
recognize what it wills. Then, as a result of this public enlightenment, in the
social body there will be a union of the understanding and the will, leading to
a precise coordination of the parts, and finally to the greatest strength of
the totality. From all this arises the need for a legislator.
To discover the
best rules for society, those most appropriate for nations, it would be necessary
to have a superior intelligence which perceived all the passions of men and did
not experience any of them, one which had no connection to our nature and yet
understood it profoundly. Its happiness would have to be independent of us, and
yet willing to involve itself with ours. Finally, it would have to be one
which, in the progress of time, by managing things carefully for
its own distant glory, could work in one age and enjoy itself in another.21R To
give laws to men would require gods.
The same reasoning
which Caligula used in arguing about the facts, Plato used in his work The Statesman about right, in order to define
what he was looking for, the civil or royal man. But if it is true that a great
prince is a rare being, how rare will a great legislator be? The former only
has to follow the model which the latter has to propose. The legislator is the
engineer who invents the machine; the prince is merely the worker who set it up
and makes it operate. When societies are born, Montesquieu states, it is the
leaders of republics who create institutions, and after that it
is institutions which make the republic’s leaders.22
Anyone who ventures
to take on the task of instituting a people ought to feel that he is, so to
speak, in a position to change human nature, to transform each individual, who
by himself is a perfect and solitary totality, into part of a greater totality,
from which this individual in some way receives his life and his being, to
alter the man’s constitution in order to reinforce it; to substitute a partial
and moral existence for the physical and independent existence we have all received
from nature. In a word, he must remove from the man his own powers in order to
provide him ones which are foreign to him and which he is incapable of using
without the help of others. The more these natural forces die off and are
destroyed, the greater and more durable are the ones he acquires and the more
solid and perfect the social institution is as well. As a result, if each
citizen is nothing and can do nothing except with all the others and if the
strength acquired by the totality is equal or superior to the sum of the
natural forces of all the individuals, we can say that the legislation is at
the highest point of perfection it can attain.
The legislator is,
in every respect, an extraordinary man in the state. If that is what he ought
to be thanks to his genius, he is no less so thanks to the work he does, which
is not that of a magistrate or of the sovereignty. This office, which
establishes the republic, does not enter into its constitution. It is a particular
and superior function which has nothing in common with controlling human beings.
For if a person who commands men ought not to command the laws, then the person who commands the laws should no longer issue
orders to men. Otherwise his laws, ministers of his passions, would often serve
merely to perpetuate his injustices, and he would never be able to prevent
particular opinions from damaging the sanctity of his work.
When Lycurgus gave
laws to his homeland, he began by abdicating the kingship. It was the custom of
most Greek city states to entrust the establishment of their laws to foreigners.
Modern republics in Italy have often imitated this practice.
The republic of Geneva did the same and benefitted from it.23R In its finest period
Rome witnessed within the state a rebirth of all the crimes of tyranny and saw
itself nearing destruction because it had put legislative authority and
sovereign power together in the same hands.
However, the decemvirs never
arrogated to themselves the right to have any law passed on
their authority alone.24 “Nothing of what
we propose to you,” they used to say to the people,
“can pass into law without your consent. Romans, be yourselves the authors of
the laws that are to create your happiness.”
Therefore, the
person who draws up the laws does not have or should not have any right to
legislate, and a people cannot deprive itself of this incommunicable right,
even if it wishes to, because according the fundamental pact it is only the
general will which imposes obligations on individuals and because we can never
be certain that a particular will conforms with the general will until we have
submitted it to the free votes of the people. I have already stated that, but
it is worth repeating.
And so in the task
of making legislation we find simultaneously two apparently incompatible
things: an enterprise which is beyond human powers and, to carry it out, an authority
which is no authority.
There is another
difficulty which merits attention. Wise men who wish to use their own language
rather than popular speech to communicate with common folk would be incapable
of making themselves understood. For there are thousands of
kinds of ideas which cannot be translated into the language of the people.
Views that are too general and objects that are too far away are equally beyond
its grasp. Each individual, having no taste for any form of government other
than the one which relates to his own particular interest, has difficulty recognizing
the advantages he is to derive from the continual privations imposed by good
laws. In order for an emerging people to be capable of appreciating the sound
principles of politics and to follow the fundamental rules of statecraft, the
effect would have to become the cause. The social spirit, which should be the
work of the established institution, would have to preside over the institution
itself, and, before there were laws, men would have to be what they are to become
thanks to those laws. And so, since the legislator cannot use force or reason,
he has to have recourse to an authority of a different order, something which
can constrain without violence and persuade without convincing.
That is what in
every age has forced the fathers of nations to resort to heavenly intervention
and to credit the gods with their own wisdom, so that the people, subject to
the laws of the state, just as they are to the laws of nature, by acknowledging
the same power in the creation of man and of the city, freely obey and
dutifully bear the yoke of public happiness.
The legislator puts
the decisions of this sublime reasoning, which extends beyond the reach of
ordinary men, into the mouths of the immortals, so that those whom human
prudence cannot budge will be drawn in by divine authority.25R But not everyone
can make the gods speak or be believed when he announces he is their interpreter.
The great soul of the legislator is the true miracle which has to prove his
mission. Any man can engrave stone tablets, or purchase an oracle, or pretend
to have secret dealings with some god, or train a bird to speak in his ear, or
find other crude ways of impressing the people. Someone who knows nothing but
things like this will perhaps be able to collect by chance a troop of fools,
but he will never found an empire, and his extravagant achievement will soon
die with him. Empty shows create a passing bond; only wisdom can make it lasting.
Judaic law, which still endures, and the law of the child of Ishmael, which has
governed half the world for ten centuries, still proclaim today the great men
who dictated them, and while proud philosophy or the blind spirit of sectarianism
sees in these men nothing but fortunate imposters, the genuine political
thinker admires in what they established that great and
powerful genius which presides over enduring institutions.26
From all of this we
should not conclude, with Warburton, that among us politics and religion have a
common object, but rather that in the early years of a nation
one serves as an instrument for the other.27
Just as an
architect, before raising a large edifice, examines and tests the soil, in
order to see if it can bear the weight of the structure, so the wise teacher
does not begin by drawing up laws which are good in themselves; instead, he
first examines whether the population for whom they are intended is equipped to
support them. That was the reason Plato refused to give laws to the Arcadians
and to the Cyrenians. He knew that these two peoples
were rich and incapable of tolerating equality. And that is why one sees good
laws and bad men in Crete, because Minos had imposed
discipline on nothing but a vice-riddled people.
A thousand nations
that were incapable of ever tolerating good laws have enjoyed an earthly brilliance, and even those which could have endured them
would have been able to do so for only a very short period of their
existence. Populations, like men, are docile only when they are young.28 As they grow older, they become incorrigible.
Once customs have been established and prejudices have taken root, it is a
dangerous and futile business to wish to reform them. The people cannot bear
even having someone touch their faults in order to get rid of them, like those
stupid and cowardly invalids who tremble at the sight of a doctor.
That does not mean
that in the life of a state there are not sometimes violent epochs when
revolutions, like some illnesses which overwhelm men’s minds and remove their
memory of the past, do to the people what certain
critical events do to individuals, when a horror of the past takes the place of
forgetting, and when the state, set ablaze by civil wars, is, so to speak,
reborn from its own ashes and, eluding death’s embrace, recaptures the vigour
of youth. Sparta was like that at the time of Lycurgus, as was Rome after the Tarquins and, in our own times, Holland and
Switzerland after the expulsion of the tyrants.29
But these events are
rare. They are exceptions, whose cause is always found in the particular
constitution of the state concerned. They cannot take place even twice for the
same population. For it can make itself free as long as it is merely barbarous,
but it cannot do that anymore when its civic springs are exhausted. In such a
case, troubles can destroy the state, without revolutions being able to
re-establish it, and as soon as its links are broken, it falls apart and no
longer exists. From that point on, it requires a master and not a liberator.
Free people, remember this precept: Liberty can be attained, but it can never
be recovered.
For nations, as for
men, there is a time of maturity which one must wait for before
subjecting people to laws.30 But the maturity
of a people is not always easy to recognize, and if one anticipates it, the
work is ruined. One people can be disciplined as it is emerging; another cannot
be disciplined after ten centuries. The Russians will never be truly civilized
because they were civilized too soon. Peter the Great had a genius for imitation,
but lacked true genius, the kind that creates and makes everything
out of nothing.31 Some of the things
he did were good, but most were out of place. He saw that his populace was barbarous.
He did not see that it was not ripe for civilization. He wanted to civilize it
when the only thing necessary was to harden it. His first wish was to create
Germans and Englishmen, when he had to begin by creating Russians. By convincing
his subjects they were something they were not, he prevented them from ever becoming
what they could have been. This is the way a French private tutor trains his
pupil to shine brilliantly for a moment in his infancy and then never amount to
anything. The Russian Empire will want to conquer Europe and will itself be conquered. The Tartars, its subjects or its
neighbours, will become its masters and ours. This revolution seems to me inevitable.
All the kings of Europe are working together to hasten the day.
Chapter 9
On the People (continued)
Just as nature has
set limits to the stature of a well-developed man, beyond which she creates
only giants or dwarfs, so in the same way, where the best constitution of a
state is concerned, there are limits to the size it can have, so that it is
neither too large to be capable of being well governed nor too small to be capable
of maintaining itself on its own. In every political body there is a maximum strength which it cannot exceed
and which it often reduces by increasing in size. The more the social bond expands,
the more it relaxes, and, in general, a small state is proportionally stronger
than a large one.
A thousand
arguments demonstrate the truth of this principle. First of all, when long distances
are involved, administration becomes more difficult, just as a weight become
heavier at the end of a longer lever. Administration also becomes more onerous
as its levels increase, for, to begin with, each town has its own, paid for by
the people, each district has its own, also paid for by the people, after that
each province, then the large governing bodies—the satrapies, the vice-regal districts—the
higher one goes the more one always has to pay, always at the expense of the
unfortunate people. Finally comes the supreme administration,
which crushes everything. So many surcharges constantly wear down the subjects.
Far from being better governed by all these different levels, they are ruled
worse than if they had over them only a single authority. In the meantime,
there are hardly any resources left to deal with emergencies, and when they
must turn to these, the state is always on the eve of ruin.
That is not all.
Not only is the government less energetic and less prompt in enforcing observance
of the laws, preventing irritations, correcting abuses, and preventing seditious
enterprises that can develop in distant locations, but the populace has less
affection for its leaders, whom it never sees, for the homeland, which, in its
eyes, is like the world, and for its fellow citizens, most of whom are
strangers. The same laws cannot be appropriate for so many different provinces,
which have dissimilar customs, live under very different climates, and cannot
tolerate the same form of government. Different laws create nothing but trouble
and confusion among populations living under the same leaders and in constant
communication with each other. They intermingle and intermarry, are subjected
to other customs, and never know whether their heritage is truly their own.
Talents are buried, virtues ignored, and vices unpunished in this multitude of
people unknown to one another whom the seat of the supreme administration gathers
together in one place. Overwhelmed with business, the leaders see nothing for
themselves, and clerks govern the state. Finally, those measures which must be
adopted to maintain the general authority, which so many distant officials wish
to evade or meddle with, absorb all the energies of the public, and there is
nothing left for the welfare of the people and scarcely any for its defense in
time of need. Thus, a body which is too large for its constitution collapses
and dies, crushed under its own weight.
On the other hand,
the state should give itself a certain foundation in order to have stability,
to withstand the tremors it will inevitably experience and the efforts it will
be forced to make to maintain itself. For all peoples have a kind of
centrifugal force, thanks to which they are constantly working against one another
and tending to expand at the expense of their neighbours, like
the vortices of Descartes.32 In this way, the
weak nations run the risk of being soon swallowed up, and it is almost impossible
for any of them to preserve itself, except by
establishing between it and all the others some form of equilibrium, which
makes the pressure on all sides just about equal.
From this we see
that there are reasons to expand and reasons to contract, and finding the
proportion between the two most advantageous for the preservation of the state
is not the least of the political thinker’s talents. In general, we can say
that the arguments for expansion, which are merely external and relative, ought
to be subordinate to the arguments for contraction, which are internal and absolute.
A healthy and strong constitution is the first thing one has to look for, and
one should rely more on the vigour born from a good government than on the resources
provided by a large territory.
One might add that
we have seen states established in such a way that the need to conquer made its
way even into their constitution and that, in order to maintain themselves, they were forced continuously to expand. Perhaps
they congratulated themselves a great deal for this fortunate necessity, which,
nonetheless, showed them, along with the limits of their greatness, the inevitable
moment of their fall.
Chapter 10
On the People (continued)
One can measure a
body politic in two ways, namely, by the extent of its territory and by the size
of its population, and between these two measurements there is an appropriate relationship
for providing the true grandeur of a state. People create the state, and the
land nourishes the people. The proper relationship, therefore, is one in which
the land is sufficient to maintain its inhabitants and there are as many inhabitants
as the land can sustain. It is in this proportion that the maximum strength of a given number of people is found. For if there
is too much land, guarding it is an onerous task, it is inadequately cultivated,
and it produces an unnecessary surplus. This is the short-term cause of
defensive wars. If there is not enough land, the state finds itself relying on
its neighbours for its additional needs. And this is the short-term cause of offensive
wars. Any population that, given its position, has no alternative other than commerce
or war is inherently weak. It depends upon its neighbours, and it depends upon
events. It never has anything other than an uncertain and short existence. Either
it conquers and changes the situation, or it is conquered and becomes nothing.
It can preserve its freedom only by being insignificant or great.
It is impossible to
provide by calculation a fixed relationship between the extent of territory and
the number of people that makes them mutually appropriate, both because of the
differences which exist in the quality of land, the degree of its fertility,
the nature of what it produces, and the influence of climate and because of the
differences one notices in the temperaments of the people who inhabit the land,
some of whom consume little in a fertile country, while others consume a great
deal on a poor soil. One must also take into account the greater or lesser
fecundity of women, the things the country can have which are more or less
favourable to the population, and the number of people the legislator can hope
to bring together there through the institutions he establishes. As a result,
he should not base his judgment on what he sees but on what he foresees, nor should he focus on the actual state of the
population as much as on what it should naturally attain. Finally, there are a
thousand situations where the particular features of a place demand or permit
one to include more territory than seems necessary. Thus, one would extend it a
great deal in mountainous country, where nature’s productions—that is, woods
and pastures—demand less work, where experience shows that women are more
fertile than on the plains, and where a large tract of sloping soil provides
only a small area of flat land, the one place one has to rely on for vegetation.
By contrast, populations can contract by the edge of the sea, even among rocks
and almost barren sands, because for them fishing can compensate, in large
part, for the lack of land crops and because people need to be closer together
to repel pirates. In addition, it is easier, thanks to colonies, to relieve the
land when its population is excessive.
To these conditions
for establishing a people, we must add one which cannot make up for any of the
others but without which they are all useless, and that is that the people
enjoy abundance and peace. For the period when a state is being organized is
like the moment when a battalion is moving into formation—at that moment the
body of people is least capable of resisting and most easily destroyed. Resistance
is more effective in a state of absolute disorder than during a moment of fermentation,
when each person is concerned about his own position and not about the danger.
If war, famine, or sedition occurs at this critical time, the state is inevitably
overthrown.
This does not mean
that many governments have not been established during these storms, but in
such cases it is these governments themselves which destroy the state. Usurpers
always bring with them or choose these troubled times and take advantage of the
public terror to get destructive laws passed, which the people would never
adopt when their minds were calm. The choice of moment for establishing laws is
one of the most reliable criteria by which one can distinguish the work of a
legislator from that of a tyrant.
What people, then,
is well suited for legislation? A population that finds itself already linked
by some unity of origin, interest, or convention and has not yet borne the genuine
yoke of laws; one that does not have deeply rooted customs or superstitions,
that has no fear of being overwhelmed by a sudden invasion, and that, without entering
into its neighbours’ quarrels, can resist each of them on its own or get the
assistance of one to repel another; a populace in which each member can be
known to all and where there is no need to load a man with a burden greater
than one man can bear; one that can get along without other
nations and that all other nations can get along without33R; one that is neither
rich nor poor and could survive on its own; and finally one that unites the
firmness of an ancient people with the docility of a new one. What makes the
work of legislation difficult is not so much what has to be established as what
has to be destroyed, and what makes success so rare is the impossibility of
finding natural simplicity linked to the needs of society. All these
conditions, it is true, are difficult to find in combination; that is why we
see few well-constituted states.
In Europe there is
still one country capable of having legislation enacted—the island of Corsica.
The courage and persistence with which this brave people has
been able to recover and defend its liberty would richly deserve some wise man
to teach the people how to preserve it. I have a feeling that
one day this little island will astound Europe.34
Chapter 11
On the Various Systems of Legislation
If we look for what
precisely makes up the greatest good of all, which ought to be the goal of
every system of legislation, we will discover that it comes down to these two
principal objects: liberty and equality. Liberty, because all
particular dependency is that much force removed from the body of the state,
and equality, because liberty cannot survive without it.
I have already
stated what civil liberty is. As far as equality is concerned, by this word we
should understand, not that the degrees of power and wealth are to be
absolutely the same, but that, with respect to power, it does not rise to the
level of any violence and is never exercised except by virtue of rank and the
laws, and that, with respect to wealth, no citizen is rich enough to be able to
purchase another, and none is so poor that he is forced to sell himself. This
assumes, on the part of the great, moderation in goods and influence, and, on the part of the lower groups, moderation in avarice and covetousness.35R
This equality, they
say, is a speculative chimera which cannot exist in practice. But if abuse is
inevitable, does it follow that we must not at least regulate it? It is
precisely because the force of circumstance always tends to destroy equality
that the power of legislation should always strive to maintain it.
But these general
objectives of every good institution should be modified in each country by the
relationships which arise, as much from the local situation as from the character
of the inhabitants, and it is on the basis of these relationships that one must
assign to each people the particular institutional system which is the best,
not perhaps in itself, but in the state for which it is destined. For example,
is the soil infertile and unproductive or the country too crowded for its inhabitants?
Turn to industry and crafts; you will be exchanging their products for the
commodities you lack. By contrast, are you living in rich plains and on fertile
slopes? Or in a fine territory do you lack inhabitants? Put your effort into
agriculture, which increases the population, and get rid of the crafts, which
would only result in emptying the countryside of people, by grouping
together in a few places in the territory the few inhabitants there are.36R Do you live on
extensive and accessible coastlines? Cover the sea with ships, and cultivate
trade and navigation. You will have a brilliant and short existence. Does the
sea on your coasts wash nothing but almost inaccessible rocks? Remain barbarous
and feed yourselves on fish: you will have a more peaceful, perhaps a better,
and certainly a happier life. Briefly put, other than the principles common to
everyone, each people has within itself some cause which organizes it in a
particular manner and makes its legislation appropriate only to it. That is why
the Hebrew people long ago and, more recently, the Arabs have had religion as
their main purpose, the Athenians had literature and the arts, Carthage and
Tyre had trade, Rhodes had shipping, Sparta had war, and Rome had virtue. The
author of The Spirit of the Laws has
pointed out in numerous examples the artistry the legislator
uses to direct what he establishes towards each of these aims.37
What makes the
constitution of a state truly firm and lasting is to have the conventional
rules for behaviour observed in such a way that natural relationships and laws
always agree on the same points, and that the latter serves, so to speak, only
to strengthen, guide, and rectify the former. But if the legislator is mistaken
in his purpose and selects a principle different from the one which arises from
the nature of things—if, for example, one tends towards servitude and the other
towards freedom, one towards riches, the other towards population growth, one
towards peace, the other towards conquest—we will see the laws imperceptibly
weaken and the constitution deteriorate, and the state will not stop being
disturbed until it is destroyed or transformed and invincible nature has
regained her imperial sway.
Chapter 12
Division of the Laws
In order to
organize a totality or to give the best possible form to the commonwealth, one
has to think about various relations. First, the action of the entire body
working on itself, that is, the relationship of the totality to the totality, or
of the sovereign to the state, a relationship which, as we shall see later on,
is made up of relations of intermediate terms.
The laws which
govern this relationship bear the name political laws and are also called
fundamental laws, not without reason, if these laws are wise. For if in each
state there is only one good way of organizing it, the people who have found
that way should hang onto it. But if the established order is bad, why should
the laws which prevent it from being good be considered
fundamental? Besides, whatever the case, a people always has the authority to
change its laws, even the best ones. For if it feels like inflicting damage on
itself, who has the right to prevent it from doing so?
The second
relationship is that of the members among themselves or with the entire body,
and, with respect to the former, this relationship should be as small as
possible and, with respect to the latter, as great as possible, so that each
citizen is perfectly independent of all the others and excessively dependent on
the city, a condition which is always achieved by the same means, for it is
only the power of the state that creates the liberty of its members. It is from
this second relationship that civil laws arise.
We can also
consider a third kind of relationship between a person and the law, that is, between
disobedience and the penalty. This gives rise to the establishment of criminal
laws, which are basically less a particular type of law than the sanction for
all the others.
Linked to these
three sorts of laws is a fourth, the most important of all. It is not carved in
marble or brass but in the hearts of the citizens. It forms the true
constitution of the state, takes on new powers every day, reinvigorates or supplants
other laws when these grow old or die away, maintains in a people the spirit
with which it was established, and imperceptibly substitutes the force of habit
for the power of authority. I am speaking about morality and customs, and above
all about public opinion, a subject unknown to our political thinkers, but one
on which the success of all the rest depends, a part with which the great legislator
concerns himself in secret, while he seems to be limiting himself to particular
regulations, which are only the curved section of the arch in which morality
and customs, arising more slowly, form in the end the unshakeable keystone.
Among these various classes,
the only one relevant to my subject is political laws, which determine the form
of the government.
End of Book 2
Book 3
Before discussing
the various forms of government, let us attempt to define precisely the meaning
of this word, which has not yet been explained very well.
Chapter 1
On Government in General
I warn the reader that
this chapter needs to be read carefully and that I know nothing of the art of
being clear to someone who does not wish to be attentive.
Every free action
has two causes that combine to produce it: one is moral, that
is, the will which determines the act; the other is physical, that is, the
power which carries it out. When I walk towards an object, the first requirement
is that I wish to go there, and the second is that my feet carry me to it. If a
paralyzed person wishes to run or if an active person does not wish to, they
both will remain where they are. The motive forces in the body politic are the
same. In it we make the same distinction between the power and the will. The
latter is called the legislative power
and the former the executive power.
Nothing is done—or nothing ought to be done—without the collaboration of these
two.
We have seen that
the legislative power belongs to and can only belong to the people. It is easy
to see, by contrast, that, according to principles previously established, the
executive power cannot belong to the people in general, as lawmaker or
sovereign, because this power consists only of particular acts, which are not
the responsibility of those who make laws and consequently of the sovereign,
all of whose acts can only be laws.
The public force
therefore requires its own agent to unite it and set it to work, according to
the directions of the general will. This agent serves as a means of
communication between the state and the sovereign and acts in the person of the
general public in somewhat the same way as the union of the soul and body does
in human beings. There you have the reason for government in the state,
something people confuse with the sovereign, for which it is merely the
minister.
What, then, is the
government? It is a body established as an intermediate between the subjects
and the sovereign, for the purpose of mutual communication between the two; it
is charged with executing the laws and maintaining liberty, both civil and political.
The members of this
body are called magistrates or kings, in other words, governors, and the entire body bears the
name prince.38R Thus, those who
allege that the act by which a populace submits itself to leaders is not a
contract are perfectly reasonable. Such an act is nothing of the sort, but
merely a commission, an employed service in which the magistrates, as simple
officers of the sovereign, exercise in its name the power which it has given
them as its agents and which it can limit, modify, and take back when it
wishes, for the alienation of such a right is incompatible with the nature of
the social body and contrary to the goal of the association.
Hence, I call government, or supreme administration, the legitimate exercise of executive power,
and prince or magistrate, the man or the body charged with this administration.
Within the
government we find the intermediate forces whose relationships make up that of
the totality to the totality or of the sovereign to the state. We can represent
the latter relationship as one between the extremes of a continued proportion,
whose mean proportional is the government. The government receives from the
sovereign the orders it issues to the people. For a state to be in proper equilibrium,
it is necessary, once everything has been adjusted, for there to be an equality
between the product or power of the government, taken in itself, and the
product or the power of citizens, who are, on the one hand, sovereigns,
and, on the other hand, subjects.39
Moreover, one
cannot alter any of these three terms without immediately breaking up the
proportion. If the sovereign wishes to govern, or if the magistrate wishes to
enact laws, or if the subjects refuse to obey, confusion replaces good order,
force and will no longer act in concert, and the state dissolves and thus falls
into despotism or anarchy. Finally, given that there is only one mean proportional
between each relation, there is only one good government possible in a state.
But since a thousand events can change the relationships of a people, different
governments can be good not only for different peoples, but also for the same
people at different times.
In attempting to
provide some idea of the different relationships which can hold between these
two extremes, I will take as an example the number of a people,
for that relationship is easier to explain.40
Suppose that the
state is composed of ten thousand citizens. The sovereign can be considered
only collectively, as a body. But each particular person, in his capacity as a
subject, is considered individually. Thus, the sovereign is to the subject as
ten thousand is to one; that is say, each member of the state has, as his share
of the sovereign authority, only one part in ten thousand, although he is entirely
subject to its authority. If the population consists of one hundred thousand
men, the condition of the subjects does not change, and each one bears equally
the full weight of the law, while his vote, reduced to one in one hundred
thousand, has ten times less influence in formulating laws. Thus, since the subject
always remains a single unit, the ratio of the sovereign to the subject grows
proportionally larger as the population of citizens increases. From that it follows
that the larger the state grows, the more liberty diminishes.
When I say the
ratio grows larger, I mean that it moves away from equality. Thus, the greater
the ratio in the geometrical sense, the smaller the ratio in the common understanding
of the term. In the former, the ratio, considered according to its quantity, is
measured by the quotient, and in the latter, considered according
to identity, it is measured by similarity.41
Now, the smaller
the relationship between the particular wills and the general will, that is,
between moral customs and the laws, the more the repressive force should
increase. Hence, the government, in order to be good, should be relatively
stronger as the population increases.
On the other hand, since
the growth of the state provides agents of public authority more temptations
and more ways to abuse their power, the greater the force the government ought
to have to control the people, the greater the force the sovereign, in its
turn, ought to have in order to control the government. I am not talking here
about an absolute force, but of the relative powers of the various parts of the
state.
It follows from
this double relationship that the continued proportion between the sovereign,
the prince, and the people is not an arbitrary idea, but a necessary
consequence of the nature of the body politic. It also follows that since one
of these extremes, namely, the people as subjects, is fixed and represented by
unity, every time the double ratio increases or decreases, the simple ratio increases
or decreases in a similar manner, and that as a result the middle term is
changed. This goes to show that there is no single, unique, and absolute constitution
for a government, but that there can be as many governments
with different natures as there are states of different sizes.42
If someone
ridiculed this system and said that in order to find this mean proportional and
form the body of the government, then, according to me, all one has to do is
take the square root of the number of people, I would reply that here I am
taking this number only as an example, that the relationships I am talking
about are not measured solely by the number of men, but in general by the
amount of action, which is a combination of a great many causes, and in
addition, that if, in order to express myself more concisely, I momentarily
borrow terms from geometry, I am nonetheless not ignorant of the fact that geometric
precision has no place in assessing moral quantities.
The government is
on a small scale what the body politic that includes it is on a large one. It
is a moral person endowed with certain faculties, active like the sovereign, passive
like the state, and capable of being broken down into other similar relationships,
which give rise, as a result, to a new proportion, within which is yet another,
according to the arrangement of departments, until one reaches an indivisible
middle term, that is to say, a single leader or supreme magistrate, who may be
represented in the middle of this progression as the unity between the series
of fractions and the series of whole numbers.
Without burdening
ourselves with this multiplication of terms, let us be content to look upon the
government as a new body in the state, distinct from the people and the sovereign
and intermediate between the two.
There is this
essential difference between these two bodies: the state exists by itself, and
the government exists only through the sovereign. Hence, the dominant will of
the prince is not or should not be anything other than the general will or the
law; his force is merely the public force concentrated in him. As soon as he
wishes to derive from himself the authority for some absolute and independent
act, the links holding everything together begin to loosen. If it should
finally happen that the prince has a particular will more active than the will
of the sovereign and that he uses the public force in his hands to obey this
particular will, so that one has, as it were, two sovereigns, one by right and
the other in fact, at that instant the social union would vanish and the body
politic would be dissolved.
However, in order
for the body of the government to exist and have a real life that distinguishes
it from the body of the state and in order for all its members to be able to
act in concert and to meet the purpose for which it was established, it must possess
a particular self, a sensibility
common to its members, a force, a unique will which tends to its preservation.
This particular existence presupposes assemblies, councils, a power of deliberation
and decision-making, rights, titles, and privileges belonging exclusively to
the prince, which make the position of the magistrate more honourable as it
becomes more onerous. The difficulties stem from the manner of organizing this
subordinate totality within the greater totality, in such a way that the government
does not impair the general constitution by reinforcing its own, that it always
distinguishes its particular power, which is intended for its own preservation,
from the power of the public, which is intended for the preservation of the
state, and that, simply put, it is always prepared to sacrifice the government
to the people and not the people to the government.
Moreover, although
the artificial body of the government is the work of another artificial body
and has, in a sense, only a borrowed and subordinate life, this does not hinder
it from being able to act with more or less vigour or speed, or from enjoying,
so to speak, more or less robust health. Finally, without straying directly
from the purpose for which it was established, it can deviate from it to a
greater or lesser extent, depending on the manner in which it was constituted.
From all these
variables arise the different relationships which the government ought to have
with the body of the state, in accordance with the accidental and particular
relationships through which this state itself is modified. For often the government
which is inherently the best will become the most pernicious, if its
relationships are not adjusted, according to the defects in the body politic to
which it belongs.
Chapter 2
On the Principle that Determines the Various Forms
of Government
To set down the
general cause of these differences, we must here distinguish between the prince
and the government, just as I made a distinction earlier between the state and
the sovereign.
The body of
magistrates can be composed of a larger or smaller number of members. We have
stated that the ratio of the sovereign to the subjects increased proportionally
with an increase in population, and by a clear analogy, we can say the same
thing about the government in relation to the magistrates.
Now, since the
total power of the government is always the power of the state, it does not
vary. From this it follows that the more of this power it uses on its own
members, the less power it will have left to deal the people as a whole.
Therefore, the more
numerous the magistrates, the weaker the government. Since this principle is fundamental,
let me strive to explain it more clearly.
In the person of
the magistrate, we can distinguish three essentially different wills: first,
the will belonging to the individual, which tends to seek only his own
particular advantage; second, the communal will of the magistrates, which has a
unique relationship to what is of benefit to the prince, something we can call
a corporate will, which is general in relation to the government and particular
in relation to the state, of which the government is a part; and third, the
will of the people or the sovereign will, which is general, both with respect
to the state considered as the totality and with respect to the government considered
as part of the totality.
In a perfect piece
of legislation, the particular or individual will should be non-existent, the
corporate will belonging to the government should be very subordinate, and consequently,
the general or sovereign will should always dominate and serve as the only
guide for all the others.
According to
natural order, however, these different wills become more active as they become
more concentrated. Hence, the general will is always the weakest, the corporate
will is in second place, and the individual will is the most important of all,
so that in the government each member is first himself, then a magistrate, and
then a citizen, a ranking directly opposed to the one required by the social
order.
Once we assume
this, if the entire government is in the hands of a single man, then the
particular will and the corporate will are perfectly united, and thus the
latter has the highest level of intensity possible. Now, since the use of force
depends upon the degree of the will and since the absolute power of the government
does not change, it follows that most active government is that of a single person.
But now, by
contrast, let us combine the government and the legislative authority, by making
the sovereign the prince and all the citizens so many magistrates. In that case,
once the corporate will is merged with the general will, the former is not
going to be any more active than the latter and will leave the particular will
with all its force. Thus, the government, which always has the same absolute
power, will be at its minimum level
of relative force or activity.
These relationships
are incontestable, and still other considerations serve to confirm them. For
example, it is clear that each magistrate is more active in his corporate group
than each citizen is in his and that, as a result, the
particular will has considerably more influence on acts of government than on
those of the sovereign. For each magistrate is almost always charged with some
function of government; whereas, each citizen, considered
individually, carries out no function of sovereignty. Moreover, the more the
state expands, the greater its real power grows, although that does not increase
in proportion to its growth. But if the state remains the same, the magistrates
could well increase in number, and yet the government does not thereby acquire
any more real force, because its power is that of the state, an amount which is
always remains the same. Thus, the relative power or activity of the government
diminishes, while its absolute or real power cannot increase.
It is also certain
that the more people there are in charge of expediting public business, the
slower the process becomes and that by emphasizing prudence too much, we pay insufficient
attention to fortune, let slip an opportunity, and by deliberation, often lose
the fruits of deliberation.
I have just
established that the government grows proportionally more lax as the number of
magistrates increases, and I demonstrated above that the more numerous the
population, the more the force of restraint should increase. From that it follows
that the ratio of a magistrate to the government should be the inverse of the
ratio of a subject to the sovereign, in other words, that the larger the state
grows, the more the government should contract, in such a way that the number
of leaders decreases in proportion to the increase in the population.
I should add that
here I am talking only about the relative power of the government and not about
its rectitude. For, by contrast, the greater the number of magistrates, the
more the corporate will of the government approaches the general will; whereas,
under a single magistrate this same corporate will, as I have said, is merely a
particular will. Thus, we lose on one side what we can gain on the other, and
the art of the legislator is to know how to fix the point where the power and
the will of the government, which are always inversely related, are combined in
the relationship most advantageous to the state.
Chapter 3
Division of Governments
We saw in the
previous chapter why we distinguish the various types or forms of government by
the number of members who make them up. We still have to see in this chapter
how these distinctions are made.
First of all, the
sovereign can commit the duties of the government to all the people or to the
majority of them, so that there are more citizen magistrates than ordinary individual
citizens. This form of government we call a democracy.
Alternatively, the
sovereign can restrict the government to the hands of a small number, so that
there are more ordinary citizens than magistrates. We call this form of government
an aristocracy.
Finally, the
sovereign can concentrate the entire government in the hands of a single magistrate
exclusively, from whom all the others derive their power. This third form, the
most common, we call a monarchy or
royal government.
We should observe
that all these forms, or at least the first two, can be adjusted to a greater
or lesser extent and even offer considerable latitude. For democracy can
include all the people or be restricted to half. Aristocracy, in its turn, can
be restricted indeterminately from half the people down to the smallest number.
Even monarchy can be divided up. Sparta always had two kings, as its constitution
stipulated, and we know that in the Roman Empire there were up to eight
emperors at a time, and yet we could not claim that the empire was divided.
Thus, there is a point at which each form of government merges with the next,
and it is clear that under these three labels alone, government is, in fact,
capable of having as many different forms as the state has citizens.
What is more, since
this same government can, in certain respects, be subdivided into other parts,
one administered in one way, another in a different way, the combinations of
these three forms can produce a multitude of mixed forms, each of which can be
multiplied by all the simple forms.
In every age people
have argued a great deal about the best form of government, without taking into
account the fact that each of them is the best in certain circumstances and the
worst in others.
If in different
states, the number of supreme magistrates ought to be inversely proportional to
the number of citizens, it follows that, in general, democratic government
suits small states, aristocratic government suits medium-sized states, and
monarchy suits large states. This rule is derived directly from the above
principle. But how does one count the multitude of circumstances which can furnish
exceptions?
The person who
creates the law understands better than anyone how it should be executed and
interpreted. Thus, it seems that we could not have a better constitution than
one in which the executive and legislative powers are combined. But that is the
very thing which makes this government inadequate in certain respects, because
matters which should be differentiated are not and, given that the prince and
the sovereign are the same person, they form, so to speak, only a government
without government.
It is not good for
the person who creates the laws to execute them or for the body of the people
to turn its attention away from a general viewpoint in order to focus on particular
things. Nothing is more dangerous than the influence of private interests on
public affairs, and the abuse of laws by the government is a lesser evil than
the corruption of the legislator, an inevitable consequence of particular
views. When that happens, once the state has been substantially changed for the
worse, all reform becomes impossible. A people that would never abuse government
would also never abuse its independence, and a people that always governed well
would have no need of being governed.
If we take the term
in its strict sense, a genuine democracy has never existed and never will. It
is against natural order that the majority govern and the minority be governed.
It is impossible to imagine that the populace would remain constantly assembled
in order to attend to public business, and it is easy to see that it could not
establish commissions to carry out this work without changing the form of the
administration.
In fact, I believe
I can set down the following principle: when the functions of government are
shared among several departments, the ones with the fewest members sooner or
later acquire the greatest authority, if only because they will find it easy to
carry out their business, a fact which will naturally bring them to this
position.
Besides, how many
things difficult to combine does such a government presuppose? Firstly, a very small
state, where the people may be easily assembled and where each citizen can
readily recognize all the others; secondly, a great simplicity of customs,
which prevents a great increase in public business and averts thorny discussions;
thirdly, a large measure of equality in rank and fortune, without which
equality of rights and authority could not last long; and finally, little or no
luxury, for luxury either is the effect of wealth or makes wealth necessary. It
corrupts rich and poor, both at the same time, the former by possession and the
latter by covetousness; it sells the country to softness and vanity; it takes
away from the state all its citizens, to make them slaves to one another and
all of them slaves to public opinion.
That is why a
famous author established virtue as the fundamental principle in a republic,
for none of these conditions could survive without virtue. But because this
noble genius failed to make the necessary distinctions, he was often imprecise
and sometimes unclear and did not see that, since the sovereign authority is
the same everywhere, the same principle should be found in every
well-constituted state, to a greater or lesser extent, of course, depending on
the form of the government.
Let me add that
there is no government so prone to civil wars and
internal agitation as a democratic or popular one, because there is none with
such a strong and continual tendency to change its form or one which demands
more vigilance and courage to maintain the way it is. In this constitution, above
all, the citizen must arm himself with strength and steadfastness and say every
day of his life, in the depths of his heart, what a virtuous Palatine said in
the Diet of Poland: I
would rather have a perilous freedom than a peaceful servitude.43R
If there were a
population made up of gods, it would govern itself as a democracy. Such a
perfect government is not suitable for men.
We have here two very
distinct moral persons, namely, the government and the sovereign, and, as a
result two general wills, one relative to all the citizens and the other relative
solely to the members of the administration. Thus, although the government can
regulate its internal policy as it wishes, it can never speak to the people
except in the name of the sovereign, that is to say, in the name of the people
itself. That is something one must never forget.
The first societies
governed themselves as aristocracies. The heads of families would discuss
public business among themselves, and the young people had no difficulty
yielding to the authority of experience. From this arose the names of priests, elders, senate, and gerontes. The
savages of North America still govern themselves in this way today, and they
are very well governed.
But as
institutional inequality prevailed over natural inequality, wealth
or power was preferred to age, and aristocracy became elective.44R Finally,
once the power and property transferred from the father to his children created
patrician families, the government was made hereditary, and twenty-year-old senators
appeared.
There are, then,
three varieties of aristocracy: natural, elective, and hereditary. The first is
suitable only for simple people, the third is the worst of all governments, and
the second is the best—it is aristocracy in the proper sense of the term.
Apart from the
advantage of distinguishing between the two powers, aristocracy also has the
advantage that its members are chosen. For in a popular government all the
citizens are born magistrates, but aristocracy restricts them to a small
number, and they become magistrates only by being elected, a method in which
integrity, enlightenment, experience, and all the other reasons for public
preference and esteem are so many additional guarantees that
one will be governed wisely.45R
Moreover, its
assemblies are more conveniently arranged, business is better discussed and
carried out in a more orderly and diligent manner, and the state’s credit is
maintained better among foreigners by venerable senators than by an unknown or
despised multitude.
Briefly put, the
best and most natural arrangement is to have the wisest governing the
multitude, when one is certain that they govern it for its profit and not for
their own. It is not necessary to multiply jurisdictions for no purpose or to
use twenty thousand men to do what one hundred chosen men can do even better.
But one must note that the interest of the corporate body begins at this point
to guide public power under less control from the general will and that another
inevitable tendency removes from the laws a part of the executive power.
As far as concerns
particular details which make this arrangement suitable, the state must not be
so small or the people so simple and upright, that the execution of the laws
immediately follows the public will, as in a good democracy. In addition, the
nation must not be so large that its leaders, scattered about in order to
govern it, can make sovereign decisions, each in his own department, and start
to make themselves independent, so that they can, in the end, become the
masters.
But if aristocracy
requires somewhat fewer virtues than does a government by the people, it also
demands others unique to it, such as moderation among the rich and content
among the poor, for it seems that a rigorous equality would be out of place
there. Even in Sparta such a thing was not observed.
Furthermore, if
this form of government includes a certain inequality in wealth, that is a good
way to ensure that, in general, the administration of public business is
confined to those who are best able to devote all their time to it, but not, as
Aristotle maintains, so that the wealthy will always be the ones selected. On
the contrary, it is important that from time to time an opposite choice teaches
the people that in men’s merits there are more important reasons for preference
than wealth.
Up to this point we
have looked at the prince as a moral and collective person, unified by the
force of laws, and the agent of executive power in the state. Now we have to consider
this power consolidated in the hands of a natural person, an actual man, the
only one with the right to use it according to the laws. Such a person we call
a monarch or a king.
In complete
contrast to the other administrations, where a collective entity represents an
individual, in a monarchy an individual represents a collective entity, so that
the moral unity that constitutes the prince is at the same time a physical
unity, in which all the powers which the law has so much difficulty combining
in the other governments, are naturally united.
Thus, the will of
the people, the will of the prince, the public power of the state, and the
particular power of the government all answer to the same motive force, all the
springs of the machine are in the same hand, everything moves towards the same
goal, there are no opposing movements working against each other, and one
cannot imagine any form of constitution in which a smaller effort produces more
significant action. Archimedes seated calmly on the shore and effortlessly
pulling a large floating vessel represents for me a skilful monarch governing
his vast estates from his study and making everything move while he appears immobile.
But if there is no
government which has more energy, there is none in which the particular will
has more influence and more easily dominates the others. Everything moves towards
the same goal—that is true—but this goal is not that of public happiness, and the power of the administration is itself constantly
working against the interests of the state.
Kings want to be
absolute, and from far away the cry goes out to them that the best way to be
that is to make themselves loved by their people. This principle is all very
well and, in certain respects, even very true. Unfortunately, those at court
will always ridicule it. The power which comes from the love of the people is
undoubtedly the greatest, but it is precarious and conditional, and princes
will never be satisfied with it. Even the best kings desire the power to be
wicked if they wish, without ceasing to be masters. Those who deliver political
sermons may well tell them that, since the power of the people is their own,
their greatest interest is served by having the people flourishing, numerous,
and formidable, but kings know very well that this is not true. Their personal
interest is, first and foremost, that the people should be weak, unhappy, and incapable
of ever resisting them. I concede that if the subjects were always perfectly
submissive, in that case the prince’s interest would be for the people to be
powerful, so that, since this power is his own, it would make him formidable to
his neighbours. But since this interest is merely secondary and subordinate and
since these two suppositions of submissiveness and power are incompatible, it
is natural that princes always prefer the principle which is most immediately
useful to them. This is what Samuel demonstrated strongly to the Hebrews and
what Machiavelli has clearly shown. By pretending to provide lessons for kings,
he gave important lessons to the people. Machiavelli’s Prince is the book of republicans.46
By considering
general relationships, we found that monarchy is appropriate only for large
states, and we find the same thing again if we examine it in itself. The more numerous
the public administration, the more the ratio of the prince to the subjects diminishes
and approaches equality, so that in a democracy it is unity or actual equality.
This same ratio increases proportionally as the government decreases in size,
and it is at its maximum when the
government is in the hands of a single person. In that case, there is too great
a distance between the prince and the people, and the state lacks a social
bond. To form that, one has to have intermediate orders: there must be princes,
great men, and a nobility to fill them. Now, none of that is suitable for a small
state, which is ruined by all these ranks.
But if it is
difficult for a large state to be well governed, it is considerably more
difficult for it to be well governed by a single man, and everyone knows what
happens when the king appoints royal substitutes.
An essential and
inevitable defect, which will always place monarchical government below
republican government, is that in the latter the public voice almost never
elevates to the most important positions anyone except capable and enlightened
men who fill the positions with honour; whereas, in monarchies those who attain
these offices are most commonly merely petty incompetents, petty rascals, petty
schemers, whose petty talents get them their important position at court but,
as soon as they get there, serve only to demonstrate to the public how inept
they are. The people makes far fewer mistakes in this choice than the prince,
and a man of genuine merit is almost as rare in the royal ministry as a fool is
at the head of a republican government. Hence, when by some happy chance one of
those men born to govern takes the helm of public business in a monarchy that
has been almost overwhelmed by crowds of these lovely officials, people are
totally surprised by the resources he discovers, and he ushers in an epoch in
his country’s history.
For a monarchical
state to be capable of being well governed, its size or extent would have to be
commensurate with the abilities of the one who governs. It is easier to conquer
than to rule. With a long enough lever, someone could shake the world with a single
finger, but he would need the shoulders of Hercules to support it. No matter
how small a state may be, the prince is almost always too small for it. But
when, by contrast, the state happens to be too small for its leader—a situation
which is very rare—it is still badly governed, because the leader, always pursuing
his grand visions, forgets the interests of the people and makes them no less
miserable by the abuse of his talents, which he has in excess, than a leader limited
by the lack of talents he does not possess. A kingdom would have to expand or
contract, so to speak, in each reign, according to the capability of the
prince; whereas with a senate, given that the amount of talent it contains is
more stable, the state can have permanent limits without affecting its administration
for the worse.
The most noticeable
disadvantage of the government of a single individual is the lack of the
continuous succession, which creates in the other two forms of government an uninterrupted
bond. Once a king dies, it is necessary to find another. Elections leave dangerous
intervals and are stormy. Unless the citizens display
an impartiality and an integrity that rarely accompany this form of government,
conspiracy and corruption come into play. It is difficult for the person to
whom the state has sold itself not to sell it, in his turn, and compensate himself at the expense of the weak for the money which the
powerful have extorted from him. Sooner or later, under an administration like
this everything becomes venal, and the peace people enjoy under kings is worse
than the disorders of an interregnum.
What have people
done to avoid these evils? They have made crowns hereditary in certain families
and have established an order of succession, which prevents any dispute on the
death of a king. In other words, by substituting the disadvantage of regencies
for that of elections, they have chosen an apparent tranquillity over a wise administration
and, rather than having to argue over the choice of good kings, they have
preferred to risk having as leaders children,
monsters, and imbeciles. They did not think about how, by thus exposing
themselves to the risks of this alternative, they are going against almost all
the odds. Dionysius the Younger spoke very sensibly when his father reproached
him for a shameful act with the words, “Did I set you an example
of such behaviour?” “Ah,” replied the son, “your father was not a king!”47
Everything combines
to remove justice and reason from a man who has been brought up to command
others. A great deal of trouble is taken, so people say, to teach young princes
the art of ruling. It does not seem that this education does them much good. It
would be better to begin by teaching them the art of obeying. The greatest
kings whom history has celebrated were not raised to reign. Reigning is a
science in which what we understand well is always less after we have studied
it too much. It is more readily acquired by obeying than by giving orders. For the most useful and the shortest method
of determining what is good and what is bad is to think about what you would have wanted to happen or not to happen if someone else were
leader.48R
One consequence of
this lack of consistency is the unpredictability of royal government which, by
organizing itself sometimes on one plan and sometimes on another, depending on
the character of the reigning prince or of those people who reign on his
behalf, cannot have a fixed goal or consistent practices for any length of
time, a variability which does not occur in the other governments, where the
prince is always the same, but which here always makes the state drift from one
principle to another and from project to project. Thus, we see that, in
general, if there is more scheming in a court, there is more wisdom in a senate,
and that republics move towards their goals with a way of looking at things
which is more consistent and better followed; whereas, every revolution in a
royal ministry creates a revolution in the state, since the principle common to
all ministers and to almost all kings is to select on every issue the course directly
opposite to their predecessor.
From this same
inconsistency we also derive the answer to a sophistical argument very familiar
to political writers defending royal government: they not only compare civil
government to domestic government and the prince to the father of the family—an
error I have already refuted—but also are generous in providing this magistrate
with all the virtues he may require. They always assume that the prince is what
he ought to be, an assumption which helps to demonstrate that royal government
is obviously preferable to all the others, because it is incontestably the
strongest and, in order to be the best as well, requires only a corporate will
more closely aligned to the general will.
However, if, as
Plato observes, a king by nature is such a rare person, how often
will nature and fortune work together to give him the crown?49R And
if the education of a king necessarily corrupts those who receive it, what
should one expect from a series of men brought up to reign? Thus, to mistake
monarchical government for the government of a good king stems clearly from a
desire to deceive oneself. To see what this government essentially is, we must
consider what it is under inadequate or wicked princes, for either they will
come to the throne with these qualities, or the throne will make them like
that.
These difficulties
have not escaped our political writers, but they do not find them problematic.
The remedy, they say, is to obey without a murmur. God, in His anger, sends bad
kings, and we must bear them as punishments from heaven. Such discussions are,
no doubt, edifying, but I would think they are more appropriate in a pulpit
than in a book about politics. What does one say about a doctor who promises
miracles and whose entire art is to urge the invalid to be patient? We are well
aware that when we have a bad government we must endure it. But the question
should be how to find a good one.
Chapter 7
On Mixed Governments
Strictly speaking,
there is no simple government. A single leader must have subordinate magistrates;
a popular government must have a leader. Thus, in the allocation of executive
power, there is always a gradation from a large number to a smaller number,
with this difference: sometimes the large number depends on the small number,
and sometimes the small number depends on the large one.
At times the
allocation is equal, either when the constituent parts are mutually dependent,
as with the government in England, or when the authority of each part is independent
but incomplete, as in Poland. This latter form is bad, because there is no
unity in the government and the state lacks a unifying social bond.
Which government is
better, a simple one or a mixed one? This question has been extensively debated
by political writers. To it I must give the same response I made earlier about
every form of government.
A simple government
is inherently better for one reason alone: it is simple. But when the executive
power is not sufficiently dependent upon the legislative power—that is to say,
when the prince has a stronger relationship to the sovereign than the populace
has to the prince—it is necessary to correct this defect in the proportion by
dividing the government, for then all its parts have just as much authority
over the subjects and their division makes them collectively less strong with
respect to the sovereign.
One also prevents
the same disadvantage by establishing intermediate magistrates, who leave the
government entirely as it is and serve only to balance the two powers and to
maintain their respective rights. In that case, the government is not mixed,
but modified.
By similar measures
one can remedy the opposite disadvantage, and when the government is too lax,
set up tribunals to concentrate it. This is done in all democracies. In the
first case, one divides the government to weaken it and in the second case to
strengthen it. For the maximum of
force and the maximum of weakness are
found equally in simple governments; whereas, the mixed forms provide an average
strength.
Chapter 8
That Not All Forms of Government are Appropriate for Every Country
Since liberty is
not a fruit of all climates, it is not within reach of every population. The
more one meditates on this principle established by Montesquieu, the more one
perceives its truth. The more one challenges it, the more one provides opportunities
to confirm it with new proofs.
In all governments
of the world, the public person consumes without producing anything. Where,
then, do the materials it consumes come from? From the work of its members. The
surplus of particular individuals produces what the public needs. Thus, it
follows that the civil state can survive only as long as people’s work
furnishes more than they require.
Now, this surplus
is not the same in all the countries of the world. In several it is considerable,
in others modest, in others non-existent, and in others negative. The relationship
between production and surplus depends upon the fertility of the climate, the nature
of the work which the land demands, the nature of its products, the strength of
its inhabitants, the greater or lesser amount they need to consume, and a
number of other similar factors which make up that relationship.
On the other hand,
not all governments have the same nature: they are more or less voracious, and
the differences among them are based upon another principle, as follows: the
further the public contributions are distant from their source, the more
onerous they are. This burden must be measured, not by the amount of the
impositions but by the road they have to take to get back into the hands from
which they came. When this circulation is quick and well-established, whether
one pays a little or a great deal does not matter. The population is always
rich, and the finances are always sound. By contrast, no matter how little the
population gives, when that little does not come back to it, the constant
giving soon exhausts the people, the state is never rich, and the population is
always impoverished.
From this it
follows that the more the distance between the people and government increases,
the more burdensome their payments become. Thus, in a democracy the populace
bears the smallest load; in an aristocracy the load is greater, and in a
monarchy it is the heaviest. Hence, a monarchy is suitable only in wealthy
nations, aristocracy only in moderately wealthy states of medium size, and democracy
only in small and poor states.
In fact, the more
we reflect on this matter, the more we find a difference between free and
monarchical states on this point: in the former everything is applied to what
is useful for the community; in the latter public and individual resources are
inversely related, with one increasing thanks to the weakening of the other.
Finally, instead of governing the subjects in order to make them happy, despotism
makes them miserable in order to govern them.
Thus, in every
climate there are natural causes on the basis of which we can designate the
form of government to which the influence of that climate leads and can even
state what sort of inhabitants it should have. Poor and barren places, where
the product is not worth the labour, should remain uncultivated and abandoned
or peopled only by savages. Places where men’s work provides only what is
strictly necessary should be inhabited only by barbarous people. All political
organization there would be impossible. Places where labour produces a modest
surplus are suitable for free people, and those where
the abundant and fertile soil provides many products for little work demand a
monarchical government, so that the prince’s luxury consumes the excess
superfluities of the subjects. For it is better that this excess is absorbed by
the government than dissipated by particular individuals. I realize that there
are exceptions, but these exceptions themselves confirm the rule, for sooner or
later they bring about revolutions that lead things back to the natural order.
We should always
distinguish general laws from the particular causes that can modify their
effect. If all the south were covered with republics
and all the north with despotic states, it would be no less true that, thanks
to the effects of climate, despotism suits hot countries, barbarism suits cold
countries, and good political organization suits intermediate regions. I recognize,
too, that, even if we accept the principle, we can argue about its application.
We could say that there are cold countries that are very fertile and southern
lands that are very unproductive. But this difficulty is a problem only for
those who do not examine every aspect of the issue. As I have already said, one
has to take into account labour, resources, consumption, and so on.
Let us assume there
are two pieces of land of equal size. One yields five units of produce and the
other ten. If the inhabitants of the first consume four and those of the second
consume nine, the surplus of the first will be one fifth, and the surplus of
the second one tenth. The ratio of these two surpluses will therefore be the
inverse of the ratio of their products. The land which produces only five units
will give twice the surplus of the land which produces ten.
But the issue here
is not that there is twice as much production, and I do not believe that anyone
ventures to propose that, as a general rule, the fertility of cold countries is
even equal to that of hot countries. However, let us assume this equality exists.
Let us, if you will, make England the equal of Sicily, and Poland the equal of
Egypt. Further south we have Africa and the Indies and further north nothing at
all. To achieve this equality in production, what a difference there must be in
the work of cultivation. In Sicily, one only has to scrape the earth; in
England, how the labourer has to toil! Now, where more hands are needed to
produce the same yield, the surplus must necessarily be smaller.
Furthermore,
consider the fact that the same number of men consume far less in hot countries,
for the climate requires them to practise moderation in order to preserve their
health. Europeans who wish to live there as they do among us all perish from dysentery
and indigestion. “We are,” Chardin states, “carnivorous
animals, wolves, in comparison with those in Asia. Some people attribute the moderation
of the Persians to the fact that their country is less cultivated, but, as for
me, I believe the reverse—their country is less abundant in commodities because
its inhabitants require less. If their frugality, he continues, were an effect
of a shortage of food in that country, only the poor would eat little, but, in
general, it is true of everyone. And people would eat more or less in each province,
depending on the fertility of the country; whereas, the same restraint is found
throughout the kingdom. They are very proud of their way of life, claiming that
one only has to look at their complexion to recognize how much it surpasses
that of the Christians. In fact, the Persians have an even complexion, with handsome
skin, fine and smooth. By contrast, the Armenians, their subjects, who live
like Europeans, have coarse, blotchy complexions, and their bodies
are fat and ungainly.”50
The closer one gets
to the equator, the less people live on. They eat hardly any meat. Their basic
foods are rice, maize, couscous, millet, and cassava. In the Indies there are
millions of people whose nourishment costs less than a halfpenny per day. Even
in Europe we see appreciable differences in appetite between the people in the
north and those in the south. A Spaniard will live for a week on what a German
eats for dinner. In countries where men have more voracious appetites, luxury
also inclines towards things to consume. In England, it manifests itself in a
table laden with meats; in Italy, you will be treated to sugar and flowers.
Luxury in clothing
also offers examples of similar differences. In climates where changes in the
season are sudden and violent, people have better and simpler garments. In
those where people dress only for show, they look more for what is striking
than for what is practical, and there the clothes themselves are a luxury.
Every day in Naples, you will see men strolling on the Posilippo in gold-embroidered coats with nothing covering
their legs.51 The same holds
true with buildings. When people have nothing to fear from the weather, they focus
completely on magnificence. In Paris and London, they want to be housed in
warmth and comfort. In Madrid, they have superb salons, but no windows which
close, and they sleep in rats’ nests.
Foods are much more
substantial and succulent in hot countries, a third difference which cannot
fail to have an influence on the second. Why do they eat so many vegetables in
Italy? Because they are good and nutritious, with an excellent taste. In
France, where vegetables are nourished with nothing but water, they are not at
all nutritious, and at dinner tables are almost irrelevant. Nonetheless, they
take up just as much land and cost at least as much effort to cultivate. It is
an established fact that the wheats in Barbary, in
other respects inferior to those in France, yield much more flour, and that wheats in France, in turn, yield more than wheats from the north. From that we can infer that,
generally speaking, there is a similar gradation in the same direction from the
equator to the pole. Now, is it not an obvious disadvantage to have equal production
but a smaller amount of nourishment?
To all these
different considerations I can add one which follows from and strengthens them,
namely, that hot countries have less need of inhabitants than cold ones and
could feed more of them. This produces a double surplus, which always favours
despotism. The greater the area occupied by the same number of inhabitants, the
harder it becomes to rebel, because people cannot concentrate themselves either
quickly or secretly and it always easy for the government to expose plots and
sever communications. But the more a numerous populace gathers together, the
less the government can usurp the role of the sovereign. The people’s leaders deliberate
in their rooms just as securely as the prince deliberates in his council, and
the crowd gathers as quickly in the public squares as the troops assemble in
their quarters. Thus, the advantage for a tyrannical government in this situation
is that it can act over great distances. With the help of the
bases it establishes, its power, like that of a lever, increases with distance.52R The power of the
people, by contrast, is effective only when concentrated. By extending itself,
it evaporates and is lost, like the effect of gunpowder scattered on the earth,
which catches fire only grain by grain. Hence, the least populous countries are
those most appropriate for tyranny. Ferocious beasts reign only in deserts.
Chapter 9
On Signs of a Good Government
Thus, when one asks
what is unequivocally the best government, one is posing a question which is
unanswerable and indeterminate, or, if you wish, a question which has as many
good answers as there are possible combinations in the absolute and relative positions
of peoples.
But if one were to
ask what sign enables us to recognize that a given people is well or badly
governed, that would be a different matter, and, now the question is a factual
one, it could be answered.
However, the matter
is not resolved, because everyone wants to answer it in his own way. Subjects
praise public tranquillity; citizens praise individual liberty. The former
prefer security of possessions, the latter security of the person; one
maintains that the best government is the most severe, the other that the best
government is the mildest; one wants crimes punished, the other wants them prevented;
one finds it good for the state to be feared by one’s neighbours, the other
prefers to be ignored by them; one is content when money circulates, the other
demands that the populace has bread. Even if they were to agree on these and
other similar points, would they have advanced any further? Since moral qualities
do not admit of precise measurement, even if there was a consensus on the sign,
how could there be about the evaluation?
As for me, I am
always amazed that people fail to recognize such a simple sign or have so much
bad faith that they do not agree about it. What is the purpose of a political association?
The preservation and the prosperity of its members. And what is the most
certain sign that they are being preserved and are prospering? Their numbers
and the population. So do not go looking elsewhere for this much disputed sign.
Everything else being equal, the government under which the citizens are
populous and multiply the most—without external methods, without naturalisation,
and without colonies—is infallibly the best. A government under which the population
diminishes and wastes away is the worst. Calculators, it is now
up to you. Count, measure, and compare.53R
Chapter 10
On the Abuse of Government and its Tendency to Degenerate
Just as the
particular will is continuously working against the general will, so the government
is constantly asserting itself against the sovereignty. The more this effort increases,
the more the constitution changes for the worse, and since there is here no
other corporate will resisting the will of the prince and establishing an
equilibrium with it, sooner or later, the time must come when the prince finally
oppresses the sovereign and breaks the social treaty. That is the inherent and
inevitable defect which, since the birth of the body politic, tends relentlessly
to destroy it, just as old age and death eventually destroy the human body.
There are two
general ways in which a government degenerates, that is, when it contracts or
when the state is dissolved.
Government
contracts when it passes from a large number to a small one, that is to say,
from democracy to aristocracy and from aristocracy to monarchy. That is its
natural tendency. If it were to go in the other direction from a small number
to a large one, we could say it was growing slack, but this reverse
development is impossible.54R
In fact, the
government never changes its form except when its spring is exhausted and
leaves it too weak to be capable of retaining its present form. Now, if a
government were to grow slack while it is still expanding, its power would
become completely ineffectual and it would have even less chance of surviving.
Hence, as the government gives way, it is necessary to rewind and tighten its
spring. Otherwise the state which it supports would fall in ruins.
The situation where the state
dissolves can come about in two ways.
First, when the
prince no longer administers the state according to the laws and usurps
sovereign power. At that point a remarkable transformation occurs: there is a
contraction, not of the government, but of the state. What I mean is that the
large state is dissolved and within in another is formed, which is composed
solely of members of the government and which for the rest of the people is no
longer anything but its master and tyrant. As a result, the instant the government
usurps the sovereignty, the social pact is broken, and all the common citizens
return by right to their natural liberty and are forced, but not obliged, to
obey.
The same situation
arises also when the members of the government separately usurp the power which
they ought to exercise only as a body. That is no less an infraction of the
laws and produces an even greater disorder. In that case, one has, so to speak,
as many princes as magistrates, and the state, no less divided than the
government, dies or changes its form.
When the state is
dissolved, the abuse of government, whatever it may be, takes on the common
name of anarchy. By way of making
distinctions, democracy degenerates into ochlocracy or mob rule, and
aristocracy into oligarchy. I would
add that monarchy degenerates into tyranny,
but this last word is ambiguous and demands an explanation.
In the common meaning of the
term a tyrant is a king who governs with violence and without regard for justice
and the laws. In the precise sense, a tyrant is an individual who arrogates to
himself royal authority without having a right to it. This is how the Greeks understood
this word tyrant, which they gave indifferently to good and bad princes whose authority was not legitimate.55R Thus, tyrant and usurper are two perfectly synonymous words.
In order to give
different names to different things, I call someone who usurps royal authority
a tyrant and someone who usurps the
power of the sovereign a despot. A tyrant
is a man who interferes illegally in order to govern according to the laws; a
despot is a man who sets himself above the laws themselves. Thus, a tyrant
cannot be a despot, but a despot is always a tyrant.
Chapter 11
On the Death of the Body Politic
Such is the natural
and inevitable tendency of the best constituted governments. If Sparta and Rome
perished, what state can hope to last forever? If we wish to form an enduring
institution, then let us not dream of making it eternal. In order to succeed we
do not have to attempt the impossible or flatter ourselves that we are giving
the work of men a stability which human things do not permit.
The body politic,
as well as the human body, begins to die from the moment
of its birth and carries in itself the causes of its destruction. But both of
them can have a constitution more or less robust and appropriate to preserving
them for a longer or shorter time. The human constitution is a work of nature;
the constitution of the state is a work of art. Men are not in a position to
prolong their lives, but they are in a position to prolong the life of the
state as long as possible, by giving it the finest possible constitution. The
best constituted state will come to an end, but later than another, unless some
unanticipated accident leads to its downfall before its time.
The principle of
political life is in the sovereign authority. The legislative power is the
heart of the state, and the executive power is the brain, which gives movement
to all the parts. The brain can collapse into paralysis and the individual
still live. A man can remain an imbecile and live. But as soon as the heart
ceases to function, the animal is dead.
A state does not
survive through its laws, but through its legislative power. The law of yesterday
is not binding today, but silence is assumed to indicate tacit consent, and it
is presumed that the sovereign constantly confirms laws it does not repeal,
when it has the power to do so. Everything it has at some point announced as
its will is always its will, unless it revokes what it once announced.
Why, then, do we
pay so much respect to ancient laws? For this very reason: we have to believe
that nothing except the excellence of these ancient acts of will could have preserved
them for so long and that if the sovereign had not constantly recognized them
as beneficial, it would have revoked them a thousand times. That is why in
every well-constituted state the laws, far from growing weak, continuously acquire
new strength: every day the bias towards antiquity makes them more venerable;
whereas, wherever the laws grow weak as they get older, we have proof that
there is no longer a legislative power and that the state is no longer alive.
Chapter 12
How Sovereign Authority is Maintained
Since the sovereign
has no force other than the legislative power, it acts only through laws, and
since laws are only authentic acts of the general will, the sovereign cannot
act except when the populace is assembled. An assembly of the people, someone
will remark, what a chimera! It is a chimera nowadays, but it was not two
thousand years ago. Have men changed their nature?
The boundaries of
what is possible in moral matters are less narrow than we think. What limits them is
our weaknesses, our vices, and our prejudices. Base souls do not believe in
great men. Vile slaves smile with a mocking air at that word liberty.
Let us consider
what can be done on the basis of what has been done. I will not speak about the
ancient republics of Greece, but the Roman Republic was, it seems to me, a
great state, and the city of Rome was a great city. The last census in Rome
showed that it had four hundred thousand citizens capable of bearing arms, and
the last population count of the empire showed more than four million citizens,
not including subject peoples, foreigners, women, children, and slaves.
What difficulties
might we not imagine in having frequent assemblies of the immense populace of
this capital city and its surroundings? Nonetheless, few weeks went by without
the Roman people gathering in an assembly, even on several occasions. The
populace exercised not only the rights of sovereignty but also some of the
rights of the government. It dealt with certain business matters and judged
certain cases. This entire people was in the public
meeting place as magistrates almost as often as they were as citizens.
If we went back to
the earliest years of nations, we would find that most of the ancient
governments, even the monarchies, like those of the Macedonians and the Franks,
had similar councils. Whatever the case, this one fact is incontestable and
answers all difficulties: arguing from what really happened to what is possible
seems like good reasoning to me.
Chapter 13
How Sovereign Authority is Maintained
(Continued)
It is not
sufficient that the populace has assembled once and set the constitution of the
state by giving its sanction to a body of law. Nor is it is sufficient that it
has established a government for all time or that it has once and for all
organized the election of magistrates. Apart from extraordinary assemblies
which unforeseen circumstances can require, there must be fixed and periodic
assemblies that nothing can abolish or prorogue, so that on a designated day
the populace may be legitimately called together by law, without the need for
any other formal summons.
But apart from
these assemblies lawfully established by their date alone, every assembly of
the people which has not been summoned by the magistrates responsible for this
action and in accordance with the prescribed procedures should be considered
illegitimate and all its actions there null and void, because even the order to
assemble should emanate from the law.
As for recalling
legitimate assemblies more or less frequently, this depends upon so many
considerations that one cannot provide specific rules about the matter. The
only thing one can state is that, in general, the more power the government
has, the more frequently the sovereign should show itself.
That may be all
very well, someone will say, for a single town, but what do we do when the
state consists of several? Shall we divide the sovereign authority or else
should we concentrate it in a single town and make all the others subject to
its authority?
My answer is that we
should do neither one nor the other. First of all, the sovereign authority is
simple and singular. It cannot be divided without being destroyed. Second, one
town cannot be legitimately be made subject to another, any more than one
nation to another, because the essence of the body politic is in the agreement
between obedience and liberty and because these words subject and sovereign are
identical correlatives, whose idea is united in the single word citizen.
Furthermore, I
reply that it is always bad to combine several towns into a single city and
that if we wish to create such a union, we should not flatter ourselves into
thinking we can avoid its natural disadvantages. In objecting to someone who
wants only small states, one should not point to the abuses of large ones. But
how does one give small states enough strength to resist large ones, the way
the Greek cities in the past stood firm against the Great King and, more recently, Holland and Switzerland resisted the House of Austria?56
Nonetheless, if the
state cannot be reduced to suitable limits, there is still one option, that is,
not to allow any capital and to have the seat of government alternate from town
to town, calling together in each of them in turn the provincial estates of the
country.
Populate the
territory evenly, extend everywhere in it the same rights, bring prosperity and
life to every place there. In this way the state will become at once as strong
and well governed as possible. Remember that town walls are built only from the
rubble of houses in the countryside. With every palace I see going up in the
capital, I imagine I see an entire region reduced to tumbledown shacks.
Chapter 14
How Sovereign Authority is Maintained
(Continued)
The moment the populace
is legitimately assembled in the sovereign body, all jurisdiction
of the government ceases, the executive power is suspended, and the person of
the lowest citizen is as sacred and inviolable as that of the first magistrate,
for where we find the person represented, we have no further need for the one
who represents him. Most of the commotions which arose at Rome in the comitia occurred because people were ignorant
of or negligent about this rule. At that time, the consuls were only presidents of the people, the tribunes no more than ordinary
speakers,57R and the senate nothing
at all.
These intervals of
suspended government, when the prince recognizes or ought to recognize a real
superior, have always been alarming for the prince, and these assemblies of the
people, which are the aegis of the body politic and the curb on the government
have, in every age, been something horrifying to its leaders, who therefore
never spare any efforts, objections, difficulties, or promises to discourage
the citizens from having them. When the citizens are greedy, timid, and pusillanimous,
more in love with ease than with liberty, they do not hold out for long against
the redoubled efforts of the government. In this way, the government’s power of
resistance constantly increases, the sovereign authority finally vanishes, and
most states collapse and perish before their time.
But between the
sovereign authority and arbitrary government, an intermediate power is
sometimes introduced, about which we need to say something.
Chapter 15
On Deputies or Representatives
As soon as public
service ceases to be the principal business of the citizens and they prefer to
serve with their money than with their persons, the state is already close to
ruin. Is it necessary to go into combat? They pay soldiers and remain at home.
Is it necessary to go to the council? They appoint deputies and remain at home.
Thanks to idleness and money, they end up having soldiers to enslave the
homeland and representative to sell it.
Concerns about
business and the arts, the avid interest in profit, and the softness and love
of comfort change personal services into money. People give up a part of their
profit in order to increase it at their leisure. Give money, and soon you will
have chains. This word finance is a
word of a slave. It is unknown in a true city. In a genuinely free state, the
citizens do everything with their own hands and nothing with money. Far from paying
to be excused from their duties, they would pay to fulfil them on their own. I
am a long way from commonly held ideas: I believe compulsory labour is less opposed
to liberty than taxes.
The better the
state is constituted, the more public affairs predominate over private matters
in the minds of the citizens. There is even considerably less private business,
because the sum total of communal happiness provides a larger share of the
happiness of each individual, so that there remains less for him to seek out in
his particular concerns. In a well administered city, each man flies to the
assemblies; under a bad government no one wants to take a single step to get
there, because no one has any interest in what goes on in them, because people
predict that the general will will not prevail, and
finally because domestic concerns absorb all of their attention. Good laws lead
to making better ones; bad laws lead to worse ones. As soon as anyone says of
state business “What does that matter to me?” one should look upon the state as
lost.
The cooling of love
for the homeland, the activity of private interests, the immense size of
states, the conquests, and the abuses of government made people come up with
the idea of having deputies or representatives of the people in the national
assemblies. This group is what in certain countries people have presumed to
call the Third Estate. In this way, the particular interest of two orders is
ranked first and second, while the interest of the public is only third.
Sovereignty cannot
be represented, for the same reason that it cannot be alienated: its essential constituent is in the general will, and the
will does not admit of representation. It is what it is, or it is something
else. There is no point in between. Hence, deputies of the people are not and
cannot be its representatives. They are merely its stewards and cannot conclude
anything definitively. Every law that the people has not personally ratified is
null and void: it is not a law. The English populace thinks it is free, but it
is seriously mistaken. It is free only during the election of the members of
parliament. As soon as these are elected, the populace is enslaved and is nothing
at all. The way it uses the brief moments of its liberty demonstrates that it
certainly deserves to lose it.
The concept of
representatives is modern. It comes to us from feudal government, from that
iniquitous and absurd government in which the human species is degraded and the
name of man dishonoured. In the ancient republics and even in monarchies, the
people never had representatives. The word itself was unknown. It is very remarkable
that in Rome, where the tribunes were so sacrosanct, no one even imagined that
they could usurp the functions of the people and that in the midst of such a
large multitude, they never attempted to pass a single plebiscite on their own
authority. However, we can get some idea of how such a crowd of people
sometimes created difficulties by what happened at the time of the
Gracchi, when one group of citizens delivered its vote from the rooftops.58
Where right and
liberty are everything, inconveniences are irrelevant. Among this wise people,
everything was carried out in an appropriately just manner. Lictors
were allowed to do what the tribunes would not have dared to
do, for the populace did not fear its lictors would
want to represent it.59
However, in order
to explain how the tribunes did represent the people sometimes, it is enough to
imagine how the government represents the sovereign. Since the law is only a declaration
of the general will, it is clear that in the legislative power the people cannot
be represented, but it can and should be represented in the executive power,
which is merely force applied to the law. This makes it clear that, if we examined
matters thoroughly, we would find that very few nations have any laws. Whatever
the case, it is clear that the tribunes, having no share of executive power,
could never represent the Roman people through the rights of their office, but
only by usurping those of the senate.
Among the Greeks,
everything the people had to do, it did by itself. It was constantly assembled
in the public square. The people lived in a mild climate; it was not greedy;
slaves carried out the work; its important business was its liberty. No longer having
the same advantages, how do you preserve the same rights? Your
harsher climates give you more needs.60R For six months of
the year you cannot use the public square, your dull voices cannot make themselves
understood in the open air, you focus more on your profits than on your liberty,
and you fear slavery far less than you do poverty.
What then? Is
liberty maintained only with the help of slavery? Perhaps these two extremes do
meet. Everything that is not in nature has its disadvantages, civil society
more than all the rest. There are certain unhappy circumstances where we cannot
preserve our liberty except at the expense of someone else’s and where the
citizen cannot be perfectly free except when the slave is thoroughly enslaved.
That was the situation in Sparta. As for you, modern people, you do not have
slaves, but you are slaves. You pay for their liberty with your own. There is
no point in your boasting of this preference; in it I find more cowardice than
humanity.
In saying all this,
I do not mean that we need to have slaves or that the right of slavery is legitimate,
since I have established that the opposite is true. I am only stating the
reasons why modern people, who think themselves free, have representatives and
why ancient peoples did not have them. Whatever the case, the moment a people
gives itself representatives, it is no longer free. It no longer exists.
All things well
considered, I do not see how it is possible from this
point on for the sovereign to preserve among us the exercise of its rights,
unless the city is very small. But if it is very small, will it not be conquered?
No. Later on I will demonstrate how one can combine the external power of a
great people with the easily administered political system and
good order of a small state.61
Chapter 16
That the Institution of Government is not a Contract
Once the
legislative power has been properly established, it is a matter of setting up
the executive power in a similar fashion, for since the latter, which operates
only by particular actions, is not essentially part of the former,
it is naturally separate from it. If it were possible for the sovereign, in its
capacity as sovereign, to possess executive power, then right and fact would be
so confused that one would no longer know what was law
and what was not, and the body politic, perverted in this way, would soon fall
prey to the violence it was established to prevent.
Since the citizens
are all equal through the social contract, all of them can prescribe what
everyone should do, but no one has a right to demand that another person do
what he does not do himself. Now, strictly speaking, it is this right, which is
indispensible for providing life and movement to the body politic, that the
sovereign assigns to the prince by establishing the government.
Several people have
maintained that this act of instituting government was a contract between the people
and the leaders it gives itself, an agreement in which the two parties
stipulate the conditions under which one is obliged to command and the other to
obey. It will be agreed, I am sure, that this is a strange way to enter into a
contact! But let us explore whether this opinion can be sustained.
First, the supreme
authority can no more modify itself than it can alienate itself. To limit it is
to destroy it. It is absurd and contradictory for the sovereign to give itself a superior; to obligate itself to obey a master is to
return to complete liberty.
Moreover, it is
clear that this contract between the populace and this or that group of people
would be a particular act, and thus it follows that this contract could not be
a law or an act of sovereignty and that, as a result, it would be illegitimate.
It is obvious, too,
that the contracting parties would be, with respect to each other, under only
one law—the law of nature—without any guarantee of their reciprocal commitments,
a situation entirely repugnant to a civil state. Since the person who has the
power in his grip is always the master of how it is applied, it would be just
like giving the name contract to the
act of a man who said to someone else, “I am giving you all my possessions, on
the condition that you give me back as many of them you please.”
There is only one
contract in the state, and that is the contract of association, which, in itself,
rules out all others. It is impossible to imagine any other public contract
that was not a violation of the first.
Chapter 17
On the Institution of Government
How then must we
conceptually grasp the act by which government is instituted? I will first
observe that this act is complex or composed of two others, namely, the
establishment of the law and the execution of the law.
In the first of
these acts the sovereign decrees that there will be a governmental body established
in this or that form. It is clear that this act is a law.
In the second, the
people appoint the leaders who will be responsible for the government that has
been instituted. Now, since this designation is a particular act, it is not a
second law, but merely a consequence of the first and thus a function of
government.
The difficulty is
to understand how one can have an act of government before the government
exists and how the populace, which is only sovereign or subject, can become
prince or magistrate in certain circumstances.
Here again we
discover one of those astonishing properties of the body politic by which it
reconciles apparently contradictory operations. For this reconciliation is
brought about by a sudden transformation of the sovereignty into a democracy,
so that, without any perceptible change and merely by a new relation of all to
all, the citizens become magistrates and pass from general acts to particular
ones, from creating law to executing it.
This change in
relation is not a speculative subtlety without practical examples. It happens
every day in the English parliament, where the Lower House at certain times
turns itself into a large committee, in order to have a better discussion of
its business, and thus becomes a simple commission of the sovereign court it
was just a moment before. The result is that it later reports to itself, as the
House of Commons, on what it has just settled in the large committee and deliberates again under one name what it has already resolved
under another.62
Democratic
government has this unique advantage that it can, in fact, be established by a
simple act of the general will. After this, the provisional government remains
in power, if that is the form of government adopted, or it establishes in the
name of the sovereign the government prescribed by the law, and thus everything
proceeds in a regular way. It is not possible to institute government legitimately
in any other manner, without renouncing principles established above.
Chapter 18
Methods of Preventing the Usurpation of
the Government
As a result of
these clarifications, it follows that we have confirmed Chapter 16: the act
which institutes the government is not a contract but a law, and those
entrusted with executive power are not masters of the people but its officers.
The people can appoint them and discharge them when it so wishes. For these
officials it is not a question of entering into a contract but of obeying; in
taking on the functions which the state imposes on them, they are merely fulfilling
their duty as citizens, without having any kind of right to dispute the conditions.
Thus, when it
happens that the people institutes a hereditary government, whether a monarchy
within a single family or an aristocracy within a class of citizens, it is not
undertaking a firm commitment, but is giving the administration a provisional
form until such time as the populace desires to set up an alternative
arrangement.
It is true that
these changes are always dangerous and that one should never touch an established
government except when it becomes incompatible with the public good. But such
circumspection is a political maxim and not a rule of right,
and the state is no more obliged to leave civil authority to its leaders than
it is to leave military authority to its generals.
It is also true
that in such a case one cannot be too careful about observing all the formalities
necessary for distinguishing between a regular legitimate act and a seditious
tumult, and between the will of an entire people and the clamours of a faction.
Here, above all, one must not concede anything to potentially dangerous cases other than what one
cannot refuse, following the full strictness of the law.63 From this obligation the prince also derives a
great advantage for preserving his power in spite of the people, without anyone
being able to claim that he has usurped it. For while the prince appears to be
using only his rights, it is very easy for him to extended them and, under the
pretext of public tranquillity, to prevent public assemblies whose purpose is
to re-establish good order. As a result, he takes advantage of a silence which
he does not allow people to break or of irregularities which he himself has had
committed, in order to assume that he has the support of those who have been
silenced by fear and to punish those who dare speak out. This is the way the decemvirs, who
were at first elected for one year and then continued for another year, tried
to retain their power in perpetuity, by not permitting the comitia to assemble any more.64 And it is by this simple means that all governments
in the world, once vested with public power, sooner or later usurp sovereign authority.
The periodic
assemblies I discussed above, are an appropriate way
to prevent or postpone such a disaster, above all when there is no need for
them to be formally summoned. For then the prince cannot prevent them without
openly announcing that he is a lawbreaker and an enemy of the state.
These assemblies,
whose sole purpose is to maintain the social treaty, should always open with
two propositions that can never be suppressed and that are voted on separately:
First: Is it the pleasure of the sovereign to
maintain the present form of government?
Second: Is it the pleasure of the people to leave
the administration to those who are presently in charge of it?
Here I am assuming
what I believe I have shown, namely, that in the state there is no fundamental
law which cannot be revoked, not even the social pact. For if all the citizens
assembled in order to break this pact by common agreement, there is no possible
doubt that the breach would be thoroughly legal. Grotius even thinks that each
person can renounce the state in which he is a member and
regain his natural liberty and his possessions by leaving the country.65R Now, it would be absurd
if all the citizens combined were unable to do what each one of them can do on his own.
End of Book 3
Book 4
Chapter 1
That the General Will is Indestructible
As long as several
men have assembled and consider themselves a single body, they have only a
single will, which is concerned about their communal preservation and general
wellbeing. Then all the springs of the state are energetic and simple, its
principles are clear and luminous, there are no confused and contradictory interests,
and the common good manifests itself clearly everywhere. All it takes to recognize
this is good sense. Peace, unity, and equality are the enemies of political subtleties.
Men who are upright and straightforward are difficult to deceive because of
their simplicity. Illusions and sophisticated pretexts do not impress them.
They are not even shrewd enough to be fooled. When we see among the happiest
people of the world groups of peasants governing the affairs of the state under
an oak tree and always behaving wisely, is it possible to prevent ourselves despising
the refinements of other nations, which make themselves famous and miserable
with so much art and mystery?
A state governed in
this manner has very little need of laws, and as it becomes necessary to
promulgate new ones, this need is universally realized. The first man to
propose them merely expresses what they all have already felt, and it is not a
question of trickery or eloquence to get passed into law what each person has
already resolved to do, as soon as he is sure that the others will act as he
does.
What leads
theorists astray is that they examine only states which have been poorly constituted
since their origin and are struck by the impossibility of maintaining there a
political system similar to the one just mentioned. They amuse themselves imagining
all the silly things a clever knave, someone with an insinuating way of
speaking, could convince the people of Paris or London to believe. They do not
realize that Cromwell would have been sent to the bells by the people of Berne and the Duke of Beaufort would have been disciplined by those in Geneva.66
But when the social
bond begins to relax and the state to weaken, when particular interests begin
to make themselves felt and small societies start to exert an influence on the
large one, the common interest changes for the worse and finds opponents, unanimity
no longer rules in the voting, the general will is no longer the will of all,
contradictions and debates arise, and the best opinion is not adopted without
disputes.
Finally, when the
state, close to ruin, no longer survives except in an illusory and empty form,
when the social bond is broken in every heart and the most vile interest insolently
adorns itself with the sacred name of the public good, at that point the general
will becomes mute, all people, guided by secret motives, no more state their
views as citizens than if the state had never existed, and iniquitous decrees,
whose purpose is merely to advance a particular interest, get passed under the
spurious name of laws.
Does it follow from
this that the general will has been annihilated or corrupted?
No. It is always constant, unalterable, and pure. But it has been subordinated
to other wills which prevail over it. Each man, in detaching his interest from
the common interest, sees well enough that he cannot completely separate it,
but his part of the public malaise appears negligible to him alongside the
exclusive benefit he means to appropriate for himself. Apart from this
particular benefit, he desires the general good in his own interest as strongly
as anyone else. Even in selling his vote for money, he does not extinguish the
general will within him. He avoids it. The fault he commits is changing the nature
of the question and responding to something other than what he is being asked.
As a result, instead of declaring with his vote “It is advantageous to the
state,” he says “It is advantageous to this man or to this party that such and
such an opinion passes.” Thus, the law of public order in the assemblies is not
so much to maintain the general will as it is to see to it that it is always
challenged and always responds.
Here I could offer
a number of reflections on the simple right of voting in every act of sovereignty,
a right that nothing can remove from the citizens, as well as on the right to
state one’s opinion, to make proposals, to divide, and to discuss, things which
the government always takes great care not to allow, except to its members. But
this important matter would require a separate treatise, and I cannot say
everything in this one.
We see from the
preceding chapter that the way in which general affairs are dealt with can
provide a reasonably accurate indication of the actual state of morality and of
the health of the body politic. The more the assemblies are governed by agreement,
that is to say, the more opinions approach unanimity, the more the general will
dominates as well. But long debates, dissention, and uproar announce the ascendancy
of particular interests and the decline of the state.
This appears less
evident when two or more orders enter into the state’s constitution, as the
patricians and the plebeians did at Rome. Their quarrels often disturbed the comitia [public assemblies], even in the
best periods of the Republic. But this exception is more apparent than real,
for then, thanks to the inherent defect in the body politic, they had, so to
speak, two states in one. What is not true about the two together is true about
each one separately. And, in fact, even in the stormiest times, the plebiscites
of the people, when the senate did not interfere with them, always passed peacefully
with a large majority of votes. Since the citizens had only one interest, the people
had only one will.
At the other
extremity of the circle, unanimity returns. This happens when the citizens, having
fallen into servitude, no longer have either liberty or will. At that point,
fear and flattery change voting into acclamations. People no longer deliberate:
they adore, or they curse. Such was the despicable way of expressing opinions
in the senate under the emperors. Sometimes that was done with ridiculous precautions.
Tacitus observes that under Emperor Otho, while the
senators heaped insults on Vitellius, at the same
time they arranged to make a dreadful noise, so that if by chance Vitellius became their master, he could not
know what each of them had said.67
From these various considerations
arise the principles according to which one should regulate procedures for
counting votes and comparing opinions, according to whether the general will is
more or less easy to recognize and the state is more or less in decline.
There is only a
single law which by its nature demands unanimous consent. That is the social
pact. For the civil association is the most voluntary act in the world. Since
every man is born free and master of himself, no one
can, under any pretext which might possibly obtain, make him a subject without
his consent. To decide that the son of a slave is born a slave is to decide
that he is not born a man.
Therefore, if at
the time of the social pact there are those who oppose it, their opposition
does not invalidate the contract; it simply prevents them from being included
in it. These are foreigners among the citizens. Once the state is established,
to be resident in it indicates consent. To live in the
territory is to submit oneself to the sovereignty.68R
Other than this
original contract, the voice of the majority is always binding on all the others.
That is a consequence of the contract itself. But someone will ask how a man
can be free and forced to conform to wills that are not his own. How are those
who oppose both free and subject to laws to which they have not consented?
My answer is that
the question is poorly framed. The citizen consents to all the laws, even to
those which are passed in spite of him, and even to those which punish him when
he dares to violate any one of them. The constant will of all the members of the state is the general will; through that they are citizens
and free.69R When
a law is proposed in the assembly of the people, what is being asked of them is
not precisely whether they approve the proposal or reject it, but whether or
not it conforms to the general will, which belongs to them. In giving his vote,
each person delivers his opinion on this question, and the declaration of the
general will is obtained by counting the votes. Thus, when an opinion contrary
to my own prevails, that proves nothing other than that I was mistaken and that
my estimate of the general will was wrong. If my particular opinion had prevailed,
I would have done something different from what I had intended and, in that
case, I would not have been free.
This assumes, it is true, that all the characteristics of the general
will are still in the majority. When they cease to be, whatever side one takes,
there is no longer any liberty.
By demonstrating
above how particular wills were substituted for the general will in public
deliberations, I have sufficiently indicated the practical ways of preventing
this abuse, and I shall have more to say about that later on. As far as the
proportional number of votes for declaring this will is concerned, I have also
provided the principles on the basis of which one can determine it. A difference
of a single vote breaks the equality; a single opposing vote breaks the
unanimity. But between unanimity and equality, there are several unequal
divisions of the votes, at each of which this proportional number can be fixed
in accordance with the condition and the needs of the body politic.
Two general
principles can help to govern these relationships: one is that the more important
and serious the deliberations are, the more the opinion which prevails should approach
unanimity; the second is that the more the matter being debated requires a
quick decision, the more one should restrict the prescribed difference in the
number of votes. In deliberations where it is necessary to reach a decision
immediately, a majority of a single vote should be sufficient. The first of
these principles seems more appropriate to laws, and the second to matters of
business. Whatever the case, by a combination of these two principles one
establishes the best ratios one can provide for announcing a majority decision.
With respect to
elections of the prince and the magistrates, which are, as I have said, complex
actions, there are two ways to proceed, that is, by choice and by lot. These
have both been used in various republics, and nowadays a very complicated
mixture of the two still takes place in the election of the Doge in Venice.
“Election by lot,”
says Montesquieu, “is part of the nature of a
democracy.” I agree with that, but why should that be the case? “A lottery,” he
continues, “is a way of choosing that harms no one; it leaves every citizen
with a reasonable hope of serving his homeland.” These are not reasons.
If we bear in mind
that the election of leaders is a function of the government and not of the
sovereignty, we will see why a lottery is the method more natural to a
democracy, where the smaller the number of administrative acts, the better the
administration.
In every genuine
democracy, being a magistrate is not an advantage but an onerous duty, which cannot
be imposed justly on a particular person rather than on someone else. Only the
law can impose this office on the person to whom the lot falls. For in such a
case conditions are equal for everyone, and the choice does not depend on any
human will. Thus, there is no particular application that alters the universality
of the law.
In an aristocracy,
the prince chooses the prince, the government preserves itself on its own, and
there voting is quite appropriate.
Far from destroying
this distinction, the example of the election of the Doge of Venice confirms
it. This combined form suits a mixed government. For it is a mistake to assume
that the government of Venice is a genuine aristocracy. If the populace there
has no share in the government, the nobility is itself the people. A multitude
of poor Barnabites has never come close to attaining
any magistrate’s office, and its nobility is merely the empty
title of Excellency and the right to attend the Grand Council.70 Since this Grand Council has as many members
as our General Council at Geneva, its illustrious members have no more
privileges than our ordinary citizens. It is certain that, apart from the
extreme disparity between the two republics, the bourgeoisie of Geneva is the
exact equivalent of the patrician class in Venice. Our natives and inhabitants
correspond to the city dwellers and the people of Venice, while our peasants correspond
to the subjects on the mainland. Finally, however one thinks about that
republic, if we set aside its size, its government is no more aristocratic than
our own. The entire difference is that, since we in Geneva do not have a leader
for life, we do not have the same need for a lottery.
Elections by lot
would have few disadvantages in a genuine democracy, where, because everything
was equal in morals and talents, as well as in principles and wealth, the
choice would become almost indifferent. But I have already said that there is
no genuine democracy.
When choice and
lotteries are both used in combination, the former ought to fill positions
which require specific talents, like military appointments, and the latter is
appropriate for positions where it is enough to have good sense, justice, and
integrity, like those with judicial responsibilities, because in a
well-constituted state these qualities are common to all citizens.
Neither lotteries
nor voting has any place in monarchical government. Since the king is by right
the sole prince and the only magistrate, the choice of his lieutenants belongs
to him alone. When the Abbé de Saint-Pierre proposed
to increase the number of the councils of the King of France and to elect their
members by ballot, he did not realize that he was proposing to
change the form of the government.71
It remains for me
to discuss the manner of giving and collecting votes in the assembly of the
people. But perhaps the history of the political arrangement of the Romans in
this matter will explain more distinctly all the principles I could set down. A
judicious reader will not find it beneath him to read in some detail how public
and private affairs were dealt with in a council of two hundred thousand men.
Chapter 4
On the Roman Comitia
We have no
well-confirmed records of the early days of Rome. It even seems
highly likely that most of the things people recite about them are fables.72R And, generally speaking,
the most instructive part in the annals of a people, the history of its founding,
is what we lack the most. Experience teaches us every day the causes which give
rise to the revolutions of empires, but since new peoples are no longer being
formed, we have hardly anything other than conjectures to explain how they were
developed.
The customs we find
established attest at least to the fact that these customs had an origin. Of the
traditions that go back to these origins, the ones that carry the greatest authority
and are confirmed by the most compelling reasons should pass for the most certain.
Those are the principles I have attempted to follow in exploring how the freest
and most powerful people on earth exercised its supreme power.
After the founding
of Rome, the emerging republic, that is to say, the army of the founder, made
up of Albans, Sabines, and foreigners, was divided
into three classes, which, as a result of this division, took the name of tribes. Each of these tribes was
subdivided into ten curias,
and each curia into decurias,
at the head of which were placed leaders called curions and decurions.
Beyond that, a body
of one hundred horsemen or knights, called a century, was taken from each tribe. From that we recognize that
these divisions, for which there is hardly any need in a market town, were at
first merely military. But it seems that an instinct for greatness led the
small town of Rome to give itself in advance a political structure suitable for
the capital of the world.
From this initial
division a disadvantage soon resulted. The tribe of Albans (Ramnenses) and the tribe of Sabines (Tatienses) remained always in the same condition, while the
tribe of foreigners (Luceres)
steadily increased, thanks to the constant arrival of foreigners, so that it
soon surpassed the two others. The remedy Servius found for this dangerous abuse was to change the basis of the division.73 He abolished classification by race and
substituted for it another based on the places in the town where each of the
tribes lived. Instead of three tribes, he created four, each of which occupied
and took its name from one of the hills of Rome. Thus, while correcting present
inequalities, he also prevented any future reoccurrence of the problem. In
order to ensure that this division would apply not only to places but also to
people, he did not permit the inhabitants of one quarter to move into another,
an action which prevented the races from intermingling.
Servius also doubled the
three old centuries of knights and added twelve others, but always keeping the
old names, a simple and judicious way of successfully distinguishing the body
of knights from that of the people, without raising a popular murmur.
To these four urban
tribes, Servius added fifteen others, called rural
tribes, because they were made up of people who lived in the country, separated
into fifteen cantons. Later on, the same number of new tribes were created, and
the Roman populace finally found itself divided into thirty-five tribes. It remained
fixed at this number until the end of the Republic.
From this
distinction between the urban and the country tribes, there resulted one effect
worth observing, because there is no other example of it and because Rome owed
to it the preservation of its moral traditions and, at the same time, the
expansion of its empire. One would think that the urban tribes would soon
arrogate power and honours to themselves and would not wait to disparage the
country tribes. What happened was just the reverse. The early Romans’ taste for
country life is well known. This taste came to them from the wise founder, who
linked liberty with rustic and military work and, so to speak, relegated to the
town arts, trades, intrigue, fortune, and slavery.
In this way, since
all of Rome’s illustrious citizens lived in the country and cultivated the
soil, Romans grew accustomed to looking only there for supporters of the
Republic. Because this was the condition of the most worthy patricians, it was
honoured by everyone. The simple and laborious life of the villagers was
preferred to the leisurely and slack life of the bourgeoisie in Rome, and the
sort of person who would have been merely an unhappy proletarian in the town
became a respected citizen by working in the fields. It is not without reason,
said Varro, that our magnanimous ancestors established
in the village the breeding ground of those robust and valiant men who defended
them in times of war and fed them in times of peace. Pliny states positively
that the country tribes were honoured because of the men who made them up;
whereas, the cowards whom people wanted to dishonour were transferred in
disgrace to the town tribes. When the Sabine Appius
Claudius came to settle in Rome, he was lavished with honours there and enrolled
in a country tribe, which later on took on his family name. Finally, freedmen
all entered the urban tribes, never the country ones, and during the entire
Republic, there is not a single example of any of these
freedmen attaining magistrate’s office, even though he had become a citizen.74
This principle was
excellent, but it was pushed so far that it finally resulted in a change and a definite
abuse within the political system.
First, the censors,
after having for a long time arrogated to themselves the right of arbitrarily
transferring citizens from one tribe to another, allowed most
people to have themselves enrolled in whatever tribe they wished.75 This permission certainly did no good and
deprived the censorship of one of its important resources. In addition, the
great and powerful all had themselves enrolled in the country tribes, while the
freedmen, once they became citizens, remained with the populace in the urban
tribes, so that, in general, the tribes no longer had any specific place or
territory. Instead, they all found themselves so intermixed that people could
no longer recognize the members of each tribe except from the registers. As a
result, the idea of the word tribe
went from something referring to property to something personal, or rather, it
became almost a chimera.
It also turned out
that since the urban tribes were more in the centre of things, they often found
themselves stronger in the comitia,
and they sold the state to those who demeaned themselves by purchasing the
votes of the rabble who made up those tribes.
As far as the curias are
concerned, the founder had made ten in each tribe. Thus, the entire Roman populace
enclosed at that time within the town walls was composed of thirty curias, each of
which had its temples, its gods, its officials, its priests, and its festivals,
called compitalia,
which were similar to the paganalia held by the rural tribes later on.
When Servius made his new division, since he could not distribute
this number of thirty curias
equally among his four tribes, he did not wish to meddle with them, and the curias became an
additional division of those living in Rome, independent of the tribes. But
there was no question of curias
in the rural tribes or in the people who made them up, because, given that the
tribes had become a purely civil arrangement and that another system had been introduced
for levying troops, the military divisions of Romulus were superfluous. Thus,
although every citizen was enrolled in a tribe, there were many who were not enrolled
in a curia.
Servius made still a third
division, unrelated to the two preceding ones, which, thanks to its effects, became
the most important of all. He separated all the Roman people into six classes, which he distinguished neither
by location nor by person, but by possessions, so that the first classes were
filled with the wealthy, the last ones with the poor, and the middle ones with
those who enjoyed a modest fortune. These six classes were subdivided into one
hundred and ninety three other bodies, called centuries, and these bodies were distributed in such a way that the
first class alone included more than half of them and the last class included
only one. Thus, the class with the smallest number of men had the largest number
of centuries, and the entire last class was counted as only one subdivision,
although by itself it contained more than half the inhabitants of Rome.
To ensure that the
people were less aware of the consequences of this last arrangement, Servius pretended to give it a military air. He inserted
into the second class two centuries of armourers and into the fourth class two
centuries of those who made instruments of war. In each class except the last,
he distinguished the young and the old, that is, those who were obliged to bear
arms and those whose age gave them legal exemption from this duty. This
distinction, rather than the one based on possessions, made it necessary to
hold frequent renewals of the census or population count. Finally, Servius wanted the assembly to be held on the Field of Mars
and all those whose age made them eligible to serve to come
there with their weapons.76
The reason he did
not follow this same division of young and old in the last class is that the
populace making it up was not given the honour of bearing arms on behalf of the
homeland. A person had to possess a hearth in order to obtain the right to
defend it, and of all those countless crowds of beggars who nowadays make the
armies of kings sparkle, there is perhaps not one who
would not have been chased away in contempt from a Roman cohort, in the days
when soldiers were the defenders of liberty.
However, in the
last class, there was also a distinction made between the proletarians and those who were called the capite censi [counted by head]. The former, who
were not entirely reduced to nothing, at least provided citizens to the state
and sometimes even soldiers during times of urgent need. As for those who
possessed nothing at all and who could not be tallied except by counting heads,
they were looked upon as completely insignificant. Marius was
the first who deigned to enlist them in the army.77
Without determining
here whether this third way of counting the inhabitants was inherently good or
bad, I think I can affirm that the only thing that could have make it workable
was the simple morality of the early Romans, their disinterestedness, their
taste for agriculture, and their scorn for commerce and for love of profit.
Where is there a modern people among whom voracious
greed, restless spirits, intrigue, constant displacements, and perpetual
changes in fortune could allow a similar arrangement to last for twenty years
without disrupting the entire state? We should also observe that in Rome
morality and censorship, which were stronger than this
system, corrected its defects and that a rich man saw himself relegated to the
class of the poor for making too great a display of his wealth.
From all this one can readily understand why people almost always
speak of only five classes, although there were, in fact, six of them. Since
the sixth did not furnish either soldiers for the army
or voters for the Field of Mars and played hardly any role in
the Republic, it was rarely thought of as having any significance.78R
These were the
different divisions of the Roman people. Let us now examine the effect these
divisions produced in the assemblies. When these assemblies were legally summoned,
they were called comitia. They were
normally held in the public square in Rome or in the Field of Mars and were
differentiated into comitia by curias, comitia by centuries, and comitia by tribes, according to which of
these three arrangements had been ordered. The comitia by curia had been
established by Romulus, the comitia by
centuries by Servius, and the comitia by tribes by the tribunes of the people. No law was
sanctioned and no magistrate elected except in the comitia, and since there was no citizen who was not enrolled in a curia, in a century, or in a tribe, it
follows that no citizen was excluded from the right of voting and that the
Roman populace was truly sovereign in right and in fact.
In order for the comitia to be legitimately assembled and
for what happened there to have the force of law, three conditions had to be
satisfied: first, the body or the magistrate who summoned the assemblies had to
be vested with the necessary authority to do that; second, the assembly had to
take place on one of the days permitted by law; and third, the omens had to be
favourable.
The reason for the first
condition requires no explanation. The second is a matter of policy. Thus, it
was not permitted to hold comitia on
festival or market days, when the country people came to Rome to conduct their
business and did not have the time to spend all day in the public square. With
the third condition, the senate held in check a proud and boisterous people and
restrained the zeal of seditious tribunes in an appropriate manner. However, the latter discovered more than one way to evade this
difficulty.79
The laws and the
election of leaders were not the only matters submitted to the judgement of the
comitia. Since the Roman people had
seized control of the most important functions of government, we could say that
the fate of Europe was governed in its assemblies. This variety in the purposes
of these assemblies gave rise to the various forms they assumed, according to
the matters on which they had to pronounce.
In order to assess
these different forms, all we have to do is compare them. In establishing the curias, Romulus
was intending to use the people as a check on the senate and the senate as a
check on the people, while exercising equal control over both. Hence, with this
form of assembly he gave the people complete authority of numbers to balance
the authority of power and wealth, which he left to the patricians. However, following
the spirit of monarchy, he nevertheless left the patricians a greater
advantage, thanks to the influence of their clients on the majority of votes.
This admirable system of patrons and clients was a masterpiece of politics and
humanity, without which the patrician class—so contrary to the spirit of the Republic—could
not have survived. Rome alone had the honour of giving the world this excellent
example, which never resulted in any abuse and which, in spite of that, has
never been followed.
Since this same
form of curias
lasted under the kings up to Servius and since the
reign of the last Tarquin was not considered legitimate,
royal laws were generally designated by the name laws of the curias [leges curiatae].
Under the Republic,
the curias,
always limited to the four urban tribes and including only the population of
Rome, could not suit either the senate, which stood at the head of the patricians,
or the tribunes, who, although plebeians, were leading
figures among the affluent citizens. Hence, the curias fell into disrepute and
became so degraded, that their thirty lictors, once
assembled, used to do what the comitia by curia should have done.
The division by
centuries was so favourable to the aristocracy that at first one does not understand
how the senate did not always prevail in the comitia with this name, in which the consuls,
censors, and the other curule magistrates were
elected.80 In effect, of the
one hundred and ninety-three centuries which formed the six classes of all the
Roman people, the first class contained ninety-eight, and since the votes were
counted only by centuries, this class by itself dominated all the others in the
number of votes. When all these centuries were in agreement, they did not even
continue to collect the votes. What the smallest number had determined passed
for a decision by the multitude, and one could say that in the comitia by centuries affairs were governed more by
the preponderance of money than of votes.
However, this
extreme authority was tempered in two ways. First, the tribunes, as a rule,
were in the class of the wealthy, which always had a large number of plebeians,
as well. Hence, they counterbalanced the influence of the patricians in this
first class.
The second way
consisted of the following: instead of having the centuries begin by voting
according to their order, a procedure which would have always made them start with the first class, they chose one
century by lot, which went ahead with the election on its own.81 After that, all
the centuries were summoned on a different day, according to their rank, repeated
the same election, and usually confirmed it. In this way, the authority of example
was removed from rank in order in to assign it by lot, in accordance with democratic
principle.
Yet another
advantage resulted from this practice. The citizens in the countryside had time
between the two elections to inform themselves about the merits of the
candidate who had been provisionally appointed, so that they did not cast their
votes without knowing about the case. However, using the pretext of speeding up
the process, the Romans finally abolished this practice, and the two elections
took place on the same day.
The comitia by tribes were, strictly speaking, the council
of the Roman people. They were convened only by the tribunes. In them the
tribunes were elected and passed their plebiscites. The senate had no standing
there. Not only that, it did not even have the right to be
present. Forced to obey laws on which they could not vote, the senators
were, in this respect, less free than the lowest citizens. This injustice was totally
misconceived and by itself was enough to invalidate the decrees of a body to
which none of its members was admitted. If all the patricians had been present
at these comitia, in accordance with
the right they possessed as citizens, and had then become ordinary individuals,
they would have had hardly any influence on a form of voting which counted
heads, where the lowest proletarian had as much power as the leading member of
the senate.
Thus, we see that,
apart from the order which resulted from these various ways of dividing up so
great a people to collect their votes, these distributions were not reducible
to inherently indifferent forms, but that each one had effects relative to the
views that made it the preferred arrangement.
Without going into
further details about this matter, we can see from the preceding explanations
what resulted: the comitia by tribes
were the most favourable to popular government, while the comitia by centuries were the most favourable to the aristocracy.
As far as concerns the comitia by curias, where the
Roman populace by itself formed the majority, because they were good only for
favouring tyranny and malicious designs, they went on to fall into disrepute.
Even seditious men abstained from using a means which made their projects too
prone to discovery. It is certainly true that the entire majesty of the Roman
people was found only in the comitia by
centuries, the only assemblies which included everybody, given that rustic
tribes were not part of the comitia by
curias and
the senate and patricians were not part of the comitia by tribes.
As for the method
of collecting the votes, among the early Romans that was as simple as their
morality, although less simple than in Sparta. Each man shouted out his vote, and
a clerk duly recorded it. The majority of votes in each tribe determined the
tribe’s vote, and a majority of the votes among the tribes determined the
people’s vote. The curias
and centuries did the same. This practice was good as long as honesty ruled
among the citizens and each man was ashamed to give his vote publicly for an
unjust proposal or an unworthy issue. But when the people became corrupt and
votes were purchased, it was appropriate for votes to be given in secret, so
that a lack of trust would discourage those purchasing votes and scoundrels had
a way of avoiding treachery.
I know that Cicero
criticizes this change and attributes to it, in part, the ruin of the Republic.
But although I am aware of the weight one should give to Cicero’s authority on
this point, I cannot agree with his opinion. On the contrary, I believe that
the failure to make a sufficient number of similar changes hastened the
downfall of the state. Just as the regimen of healthy people is inappropriate
for invalids, so one should wish to govern a corrupt people with the same laws
which are appropriate for a good people. Nothing proves this principle better
than the long life of the Venetian Republic, whose insubstantial form still
exists, solely because its laws are suitable only for wicked men.
The citizens were
thus given tablets on which each person could vote without anyone knowing what
his opinion was. They also instituted new formalities for collecting the
tablets, counting the votes, comparing the numbers, and so on. These did not
prevent people from frequently suspecting the trustworthiness
of the officials charged with carrying out these duties.82R Finally,
to prevent trickery and trafficking in votes, edicts were announced, but the
large number of these shows how ineffectual they were.
Towards the final
period of the Republic, it was often necessary to turn to extraordinary
expedients in order to make up for the inadequacy of the laws. Sometimes it was
implied that miracles had taken place, but this method, while capable of
impressing the people, had no effect on those who governed. Sometimes an
assembly was summoned abruptly, before the candidates had time to organize
their intrigues. Sometimes an entire session was spent talking, when it was
clear that the populace had been won over and was ready to adopt a bad
position. But in the end ambition eluded all such attempts, and what is incredible
is that in midst of so much abuse, this immense people, thanks to its ancient
regulations, did not fail to elect magistrates, pass laws, judge cases, or
expedite private and public business with almost as much facility as the senate
itself could have done.
When it is
impossible to establish an exact proportion between the parts making up the
state or when causes which cannot be eliminated constantly alter the relationships
among those parts for the worse, then a special magistracy is established which
does not share a corporate identity with the others. This magistracy restores each
term to its correct relationship and creates a link or a middle term, either between
the prince and the people, or between the prince and the sovereign, or, if
necessary, between both sides at once.
This body, which I
shall call the tribunate, is the preserver
of the laws and of the legislative power. Sometimes it serves to protect the sovereign
against the government, as the tribunes of the people did in Rome, sometimes to
maintain the government against the people, as the Council of Ten does now in Venice,
and sometimes to preserve the balance between the two, as the ephors did in Sparta.83
The tribunate is
not a constituent part of the state and should have no share of legislative or
executive power. But from that very fact, its power is greater, for although it
cannot do anything, it can prevent anything from being done. As the defender of
the laws, it is more sacred and more revered than the prince who executes them
and the sovereign who provides them. This was clearly evident in Rome when
those proud patricians, who always despised the people as a whole, were forced
to bow down before a simple officer of the people who had neither auspices nor
jurisdiction.
A wisely tempered
tribunate is the strongest support for a good constitution, but if its power is
even a little excessive, it overturns everything. As for being weak, that is
not in its nature, and provided it is something, it is never less than it needs
to be.
The tribunate
degenerates into tyranny when it usurps executive power, for which it is merely
the moderator, and when it wishes to administer the laws, which its only duty
is to protect. The enormous power of the ephors, which posed no danger as long
as Sparta preserved its traditional morality, accelerated corruption there,
once it had commenced. The blood of Agis, whose
throat was slit by these tyrants, was avenged by his successor. The crime and
the punishment of the ephors both hastened equally the fall of the republic, and after Cleomenes
Sparta was no longer significant. Rome also perished in the same way: the
excessive power of the tribunes, which they had gradually usurped, together
with the help of laws made to protect liberty, finally served
as a safeguard for the emperors who destroyed it.84 As for the Council
of Ten in Venice, it is a tribunal of blood, an object of horror to the patricians
and the people alike, which, far from proudly protecting the laws, no longer
serves for anything, now those laws have been degraded, except to strike blows
in the shadows, which no one dares notice.
The tribunate, like
the government, grows weak as the number of its members increases. When the tribunes
of the Roman people, who at first numbered two and later five, wished to double
this number, the senate let them do it, fully confident that it could use some
of them to restrain the others, and that is exactly what happened.
The best way to
prevent the usurpations of such a redoubtable body, a method which no government
has used up to this point, would be not to make the tribunate a permanent body
but to regulate the periods during which it would remain suppressed. These
periods, which should not be long enough to allow abuses time to grow strong,
can be fixed by the law in such a way that it would be easy to shorten them, if
need be, by extraordinary commissions.
This method, in my
view, would have no disadvantages, because, as I have said, the tribunate is
not part of the constitution and can be removed without damaging it, and it seems
to me an effective method, because a newly instated magistrate begins, not with
the power which his predecessor had, but with the power the law assigns him.
The inflexibility
of the laws, which prevents them from being adapted to events, can in certain
cases make them harmful and during a crisis lead them to bring about the ruin
of the state. The order and the slowness of procedures require a space of time
which circumstances sometimes do not allow. A thousand situations can arise
which the legislator has not anticipated, and a very necessary part of
foresight is having a sense that one cannot foresee everything.
Thus, one should
not demand that political institutions be strengthened to the point where one
makes it impossible to suspend their effect. Even Sparta allowed its laws to
slumber.
But only the very
gravest dangers can offset the danger of changing the public order, and the
sacred power of the laws should never be suspended, except when it is a matter
of the safety of the homeland. In these rare and obvious cases, one provides
for the safety of the public by a particular act which assigns this
responsibility to the most worthy person. This commission can be assigned in
two ways, depending on the nature of the danger.
If one can remedy
things sufficiently by increasing the activity of the government, one
concentrates it in one or two of its members. In this way, one is not altering
the authority of the laws, but merely the way in which they are administered.
If the peril is such that the system of laws is an obstacle to their preservation,
in that case one appoints a supreme leader who may silence all the laws and suspend
for the moment the sovereign authority. In a situation like that, the general
will is not in doubt: it is clear that the people’s primary intention is that
the state does not perish. In this way, the suspension of the legislative authority
does not abolish it. The magistrate who silences it cannot make it speak. He
dominates it, but does not have the power to represent it. He can do anything,
except make laws.
The first method
was employed by the Roman senate when, with a consecrated formula, it charged
the consuls to provide for the safety of the Republic. The second
method occurred when one of the two consuls appointed a dictator.85R Alba had provided
Rome an example of this practice.86
In the initial
years of the Republic, they had very frequent recourse to dictatorship, because
the state did not yet have a sufficiently firm foundation to be capable of maintaining
itself by the strength of its constitution alone.
Since at that time
traditional morality rendered superfluous many of the precautions which would
have been necessary in another age, they had no fear that a dictator would
abuse his authority or that he would attempt to hang onto it beyond his term.
It seemed, by contrast, that such enormous power was a burden to the man entrusted
with it, so eager was he to divest himself of it quickly, as if a position
which replaced the laws was too difficult and too perilous.
Thus, what makes me
criticize the indiscreet use of this supreme magistrate in the early days of
Rome is the danger, not of abusing it, but of demeaning its significance. For
while they made excessive use of it in elections, dedications, and purely
formal occasions, there was a fear that it would become less formidable in
times of need and that people would grow accustomed to looking on it as an
empty title, used only at empty ceremonials.
Towards the end of
the Republic, the Romans, who had become more circumspect, were as unreasonable
in limiting dictatorship as they had been previously in using it too much. It
was easy to see that their fears had little foundation, that the weakness of
the capital city at the time made it safe from the magistrates who lived inside
it, that a dictator could, in certain situations, defend public freedom,
without ever being able to attack it, and that R0me’s shackles would be forged,
not in Rome itself, but in its armies. The feeble resistance which Marius offered
against Sulla and Pompey offered against Caesar clearly showed what one could expect from the authority within the city against a force
from outside.87
This mistake led
the Romans to commit major blunders, such as, for example, not naming a dictator
during the Catiline affair. For since this involved only the interior of the
city and, at most, some province in Italy, a dictator with the unlimited
authority provided by law would have easily broken up the conspiracy, which was
snuffed out only by a combination of fortunate chance events,
which human prudence could never have anticipated.88
Instead of that,
the senate contented itself with handing over all its power to the consuls. The
result was that Cicero, in order to take effective action, was forced to
overstep this power at a critical point, and if the first transports of joy led
them to approve of his conduct, later on he was justly called to account for
the blood of citizens shed in violation of the laws, a reproach which could not
have been made against a dictator. But the eloquence of the consul carried all
before it, and he himself, although a Roman, loved his own glory more than his
homeland and sought out, not so much the most legitimate and surest way of saving the state, as the one that would give him all the honour in
this affair.89R And
so he was justly celebrated as the liberator of Rome and justly punished as a
breaker of the laws. However brilliant his recall may have
been, it clearly was a pardon.90
Furthermore, in
whatever manner this important commission is conferred, it is important to
establish that it will last for a very short period of time and can never be extended.
In the crises which lead to its implementation, the state is soon destroyed or
saved, and once the urgent need has passed, a dictatorship becomes tyrannical
or useless. In Rome, dictators were appointed for only six months, and most abdicated
before this term was over. If the term had been longer, perhaps they might have
been tempted to prolong it further, as the decemvirs did with their one-year
term. The dictator had time only to cope with the need which had led to his
election. He had no time to dream of other projects.
Just as the
declaration of the general will is made through the law, so the declaration of
public judgment is made through the censorship. Public opinion is the variety
of law administered by the censor, which he applies only to particular cases,
following the example of the prince.
Thus, the censorial
tribunal, far from being the arbiter of public opinion, merely announces it,
and as soon as the tribunal moves away from this opinion, its decisions are
empty and ineffectual.
It is pointless to
distinguish the morality of a nation from the objects it esteems, for all these
things are derived from the same principle and are necessarily interconnected.
Among all the peoples of the world, it is not nature but opinion that determines
the choice of their pleasures. Correct men’s opinions,
and their morality will purify itself. People always love what is good or what
they find good, but they make mistakes in their judgment of what that is.
Therefore, the issue is a matter of regulating this judgment. Anyone who judges
morality is judging honour, and anyone who judges honour takes his law from opinion.
The opinions of a
people are born from its constitution. Although the law does not regulate
morality, it is legislation which produces it. When legislation is weak,
morality degenerates, but in such situations the judgment of the censors will
not achieve what the power of the law has failed to bring about.
From that it
follows that the censorship can be useful for preserving morals but never for
restoring them. Establish censors when the laws are strong. As soon as they
lose their strength, everything is hopeless. Nothing legitimate has force any
more once the laws no longer have any.
The censorship
supports morality by preventing opinions from becoming corrupted, by preserving
their integrity with wise applications, and sometimes even by determining
opinions when they are still uncertain. The use of seconds in duels, carried to
a frenzy in the kingdom of France, was abolished there
simply by these words in a royal edict: “as for those who are cowardly enough
to call upon seconds.” This judgment, anticipating that of the public,
instantly determined the matter. But when the same edicts wanted to announce
that it was also cowardice to fight duels—which is very true but contrary to
common opinion—the public ignored this decision in a matter on which it had already
rendered judgement.
I have said
elsewhere that since public opinion is not subject to constraint,
there must be no trace of that in the tribunal set up to represent it.91R It is impossible
to admire too much the skill with which this resource, entirely lost among
modern people, was implemented among the Romans and even more so among the Lacedaemonians.
When a man with bad
morals offered good advice in the Spartan Council, the ephors paid no attention
to it and had the same opinion put forward by a virtuous citizen. What an honour
for one, and what a disgrace for the other, without a word of praise or blame
for either of the two! When certain drunkards from Samos defiled the Tribunal
of Ephors, the next day a public edict gave the Samians permission to be disgusting.92 A real punishment would have been less severe
than this kind of impunity. When Sparta has made a pronouncement on what is or
is not respectable, Greece does not appeal its judgments.
At first men had no
kings other than the gods, nor any government other than a theocratic one. They
reasoned like Caligula, and at that time such reasoning was correct. Changes in
feelings and ideas over a long time are necessary in order for men to be capable
of deciding to take someone like themselves as their master and of flattering
themselves that things will work out well for them.
From the mere fact
that a god was placed at the head of each political society, it followed that
there were as many gods as peoples. Two populations foreign to each other and
almost always enemies could not recognize the same master for long; two armies
busy fighting each other could not obey the same leader. And so national
differences produced polytheism and from that theological and civil intolerance,
which, as I will mention later, are naturally the same.
The fanciful way
the Greeks had of rediscovering their own gods among barbarous peoples came
from the similar habit they also had of looking upon themselves as the natural
rulers of these peoples. But nowadays the erudition which merges the identities
of the gods of various nations is truly ridiculous, as if Moloch, Saturn, and Cronos could have been the same god, as if Baal of the Phoenicians,
Zeus of the Greeks, and Jupiter of the Latins could
have been the same, as if there could have been anything in common among
chimerical beings carrying different names!
If one asks how
there were no wars of religion in pagan times, when each state had its cult and
its gods, I answer that it was for that very reason: since each state had its
own cult as well as its own government, it did not distinguish between its gods
and its laws. Political war was also theological. The departments of the gods
were, so to speak, determined by national boundaries. The god of one people had
no right over other peoples. The gods of the pagans were not jealous; they
shared among themselves the empire of the world. Even Moses and the Hebrew people sometimes endorsed
this idea by speaking of the God of Israel. It is true they regarded the gods
of the Canaanites as nothing at all, but these people were outcasts, doomed to
destruction, and the Hebrews were to occupy their
lands. But consider how the Hebrews spoke about the divinities of neighbouring
peoples they were forbidden to attack. “Is not the possession of what belongs
to your god Chamos,” said Jephthah
to the Ammonites, “legitimately your own? We possess the same
title to the lands which our victorious god has acquired for himself.”93R At that point, it
seems to me, there was a clear recognition that rights of Chamos
and those of the God of Israel were equal.
But when the Jews
were subjects of the kings of Babylon and then later of the kings of Syria,
they were obstinate in refusing to recognize any god but their own, and their refusal was looked upon as a rebellion
against their conqueror. It brought down on them the persecutions we read about in their history. We see no other examples of this before
Christianity.94R
Thus, since each
religion was exclusively linked to the laws of the state which prescribed it,
there was no way of converting a people except by enslaving it, and there were
no missionaries other than conquerors. Since the obligation to change religious
cult was a law of the vanquished, one had to begin by conquering before talking
about such things. Far from men fighting for the gods, it was the gods, as in
Homer, who fought for men. Each man asked his god for victory and rewarded him
for it with new altars. Before capturing a place, the Romans called upon its
gods to abandon it. When they let the Tarentines keep
their angry gods, the reason was that at the time they considered these gods
subject to their own and forced to pay them homage. The Romans left those they
conquered their own gods, just as they left them their own laws. Often the only
tribute they imposed was a wreath to Capitoline Jupiter.
Finally, once the
Romans had extended their religion and their gods along with their empire and
had often themselves adopted those of the peoples they had conquered, they accorded
to both the rights of the city, and the peoples of this vast empire found themselves
imperceptibly acquiring multitudes of gods and cults, which were almost the
same everywhere. That is how paganism in the known world eventually became a
single integrated religion.
It was in these
circumstances that Jesus came to establish on earth a spiritual kingdom, which,
by separating the theological system from the political system, meant that the
state ceased to be unified and caused internal divisions which have never
stopped agitating Christian peoples. Now, since this new idea of a kingdom in
another world could never have occurred to pagans, they always looked upon
Christians as genuine rebels who, beneath a hypocritical submission, were only
looking for an opportunity to make themselves independent
and their masters and adroitly seize the authority they pretended in their weakness
to respect. This was the cause of the persecutions.
What the pagans had
feared came to pass, and then the appearance of everything was transformed: the
humble Christians changed their language, and soon people saw this alleged kingdom
in another world become, under a visible leader, the most violent despotism in
this world.
However, since
there have always been a prince and civil laws, this double power has resulted
in a perpetual conflict over jurisdiction, which has made all good political arrangements
impossible in Christian states, and people have never been able to resolve the
question whether they were obliged to obey the ruler or the priest.
However, several
people, even in Europe or its vicinity, wished to preserve or reinstate the old
system, but without success. The spirit of Christianity prevailed over everything.
The sacred cult has always remained or has once more become independent of the
sovereign, without a necessary connection to the body of the state. Mohammed’s
views were very sensible, and he linked his political system together well. As
long as his form of government lasted under the caliphs who succeeded him, this
government was strictly unified and, in that respect, a good one. But once the
Arabs became prosperous, literate, civilized, soft, and cowardly, they were
subjugated by barbarians. At that point, the division between the two powers
started once again. Although it may be less apparent among the Mohammedans than
among the Christians, it is there, nonetheless, above all in the sect of Ali,
and there are states, like Persia, where it never ceases to make itself felt.
Among us, the kings
of England have made themselves heads of the church, and the tsars have done
the same. But with this title they have made themselves less masters of the
church than its ministers. What they have acquired is not so much the right to
change it as the power to maintain it. They are not its legislators but merely
its princes. Wherever the clergy is a corporate body, it is
master and legislator in its own domain.95R Thus, there are
two powers, two sovereigns, in England and in Russia, just as there are everywhere
else.
Of all Christian
writers, the philosopher Hobbes is the only one who has clearly seen the evil
and the remedy. He dared to propose reuniting the two heads of the eagle and
bringing everything back to political unity, without which neither the state
nor the government will ever be well constituted. But he should have seen that
the domineering spirit of Christianity was incompatible with his system and
that the interest of the priest would always be stronger than that of the
state. What makes people hate his political theory is not so
much what is horrible and false in it as what is just and true.96R
I believe that if
we examined the historical facts from this point of view, we would easily
refute the opposing opinions of Bayle and Warburton: the former maintains that
no religion is of any use to the body politic, and the latter,
by contrast, claims that Christianity is its firmest support.97 We could prove to the first that no state has
ever been established where religion did not serve as its foundation, and to
the second that Christian law is basically more injurious than useful to a
strong state constitution. To make myself understood, I need only provide a
little more precision to the overly vague ideas of religion relevant to my
subject.
Religion,
considered in relation to society, which is either general or particular, can
also be divided into two types, namely, the religion of man and the religion of
the citizen. The first has no temples, no altars, no
rites and is limited to the purely interior worship of the supreme God and to
the eternal duties of morality. This is the pure and simple religion of the Gospel,
the true theism, and we can call it divine
natural right or law. The other is
registered in a single country and provides its gods, its own tutelary patrons.
It has its dogmas, its rites, and its external worship prescribed by the laws.
Outside the single nation which follows this religion, everything is, from its
point of view, infidel, foreign, and barbarous. It extends the duties and the
rights of man only as far as its altars. Such were all the religions of early
peoples. We can give these the name civil
or positive divine right or law.
There is a third
and more bizarre form of religion which provides men with two legislations, two
leaders, and two homelands; it subjects them to contradictory obligations and
makes them incapable of being both devout worshippers and citizens at the same
time. The religions of the Lamas and of the Japanese are like this, as is Roman
Christianity. We can call this form the religion
of the priest. It results in a sort of mixed and unsociable law which has
no name.
Considered from a
political perspective, these three varieties of religion all have their faults.
The third is so obviously bad that to amuse oneself by
demonstrating the fact would be a waste of time. Everything which fractures social
unity has no value, and all institutions which set a man in contradiction with
himself are worthless.
The second is good,
in that it unites the divine cult and love of the laws and, by making the
homeland the object of adoration among the citizens, teaches them that to serve
the state is to serve its tutelary god. It is a type of theocracy in which
there is to be no pontiff but the prince and no priests but the magistrates.
Thus, dying for one’s country means becoming a martyr, violating the laws is
impiety, and subjecting a guilty person to public execration is
sacrificing him to the anger of the gods. Sacer estod.98
However, this form
of religion is bad, because, being based on error and lies,
it deceives people, makes them credulous and superstitious, and drowns genuine
worship of the divinity in an empty ceremonial. It is bad, too, when it becomes
exclusive and tyrannical and makes a people bloodthirsty and intolerant, so
that it breathes only murder and massacre and believes it is carrying out a sacred
act by killing anyone who does not accept its gods. That places such a people
in a natural state of war with all the others, something very injurious to its
own security.
Thus, what remains
is the religion of man or Christianity—not the Christianity of today, but that
of the Gospel, which is entirely different. In this holy, sublime, and true
religion, all men, children of the same God, recognize each other as brothers,
and the society which unites them is not dissolved even at death.
But since this
religion has no specific relationship with the body politic, it leaves the laws
with the power they draw from themselves alone, without adding anything else to
them, and in that way one of the great bonds of a particular society remains
without effect. And more than that, far from tethering the citizens’ hearts to
the state, it detaches them from it, as it does from all things of the earth. I
know of nothing more contrary to the social spirit.
People tell us that
a population of true Christians would form the most perfect society one could
imagine. In this supposition I see only one large difficulty: a society of true
Christians would no longer be a society of men.
I even claim that
this supposed society, for all its perfection, would be neither the strongest
nor the most durable. Because it would be perfect, it would lack social bonds; its very perfection would be its destructive flaw.
Each person would
fulfil his duty, the people would be subject to the laws, the leaders would be
just and temperate, the magistrates honest and incorruptible, the soldiers
would scorn death, and there would be neither vanity nor luxury. That is all
well and good. But let us look further.
Christianity is an
entirely spiritual religion, exclusively concerned with heavenly things. A Christian’s
homeland is not of this world. He does his duty—that is true—but he does it
with a profound indifference to the success or lack of success of his efforts.
Provided he has nothing to reproach himself with, it matters little to him
whether everything here below goes well or ill. If the state is flourishing, he
hardly ventures to rejoice in the public happiness, for fear of growing proud
of his country’s glory; if the state is declining, he blesses the hand of God
weighing down His people.
For such a society
to be peaceful and for harmony to be maintained, all the citizens without
exception would have to be equally good Christians. But if, by some misfortune,
there is one ambitious person, a single hypocrite, a Catiline, for example, or
a Cromwell, he will inevitably get the better of his pious compatriots.
Christian charity does not readily permit one to think ill of one’s neighbour.
The moment he finds a way of forcing himself on them by some ruse and of
grasping a share of public authority, then there you have
it, a man established in dignity, someone God wants people to respect, and
then, soon enough, you have a power, someone God wants people to obey. And the
man who is entrusted with this power, does he abuse it? That is the rod with
which God punishes His children. People would have scruples about driving out
the usurper: that would require upsetting public tranquillity, using violence
and spilling blood—none of which sits well with Christian meekness. And, after
all, what does it matter whether one is a free man or a serf in this vale of sorrow?
The essential matter is reaching paradise, and resignation is merely one more
way of getting there.
What if there is
some war with a foreign state? The citizens have no trouble marching out to
fight. Not one of them dreams of running away. They do their duty. But they
have no passion for victory. They know more about dying than about conquering.
Whether they are the victors or the vanquished, what does that matter to them?
Does not Providence understand better than they do what is right for them?
Imagine how a proud, impetuous, and passionate enemy could take advantage of
their stoicism! Set against them those generous people consumed with an ardent
love of glory and of their homeland. Imagine your Christian republic up against
Sparta or Rome. The pious Christians will be beaten, crushed, and destroyed, before
they have had time to know where they are or will owe their safety solely to
the scorn their enemy feels for them. In my view, that was a fine oath which
the soldiers of Fabius made: they did not swear to
die or conquer, but to return victorious, and they kept their oath. Christians
would never have done anything like that. They would have thought they were
tempting God.
However, I am wrong
to talk about a Christian republic. These two words are mutually exclusive.
Christianity preaches nothing but servitude and dependence. Its spirit is too
favourable to tyranny for tyranny not to use it all the time for its own advantage.
Genuine Christians are made to be slaves. They realize this and are scarcely
moved by it. The value of this short life, in their eyes, is too small.
Someone will tell
me that Christian soldiers are excellent. That I deny. Show me an example of
such men. As far as I am concerned, I do not know of any Christian soldiers.
People will cite the Crusades. Without disputing the courage of the Crusaders,
I will observe that they were far from being Christians. They were the soldiers
of the priest; they were citizens of the Church. They fought for their
spiritual country, which the Church had made temporal, no one knows how.
Properly understood, this is a reversion to paganism. Since the Gospel does not
establish a national religion, all holy wars are impossible among Christians.
Under the pagan
emperors, Christian soldiers were brave. All the Christian authors affirm the
fact, and I believe it. It was a matter of emulating the honour of pagan
soldiers. From the time the emperors were Christians this emulation no longer
survived, and when the Cross had chased away the eagle, all Roman valour
disappeared.
However, setting
aside political considerations, let us return to what is right and determine
the principles on this important point. The right which the social pact gives
the sovereign over his subjects, as I have stated, does not
move beyond the limits of public utility.99R Thus, the subjects
do not have to answer to the sovereign for their opinions, except to the extent
that these opinions are significant to the community. Now, it is very important
to the state that each citizen has a religion that makes him love his duties,
but neither the state nor its members have any interest in the doctrines of
this religion except insofar as these doctrines relate to morality and to the
duties which the person professing them is obliged to fulfill towards others. Beyond
that, each man can have whatever opinions he pleases, without the sovereign having
any business knowing about them. For, since the sovereign has no authority in
the world beyond, the fate of his subjects in the life to come, whatever it may
be, is not his concern, provided that they are good
citizens in this one.
Therefore, there is
a purely civil profession of faith, the articles of which it is the business of
the sovereign to establish, not as religious dogmas exactly, but as sentiments
of sociability, without which it is impossible to be a good
citizen or a faithful subject.100R While the
sovereign cannot oblige anyone to believe them, it can banish from the state
anyone who does not believe them, and it can banish him not because the person
is impious, but because he is unsociable, because he is incapable of sincerely
loving the laws and justice and of sacrificing his life, if need be, to his
duty. And if someone who has publicly accepted these very doctrines behaves as
if he does not believe them, he should be punished with death, for he has
committed the greatest of crimes: he has lied before the laws.
The doctrines of
civil religion should be simple, few in number, and precisely stipulated,
without explication or commentary: the existence of the Divinity, a powerful, intelligent,
beneficent, provident, and foreseeing god, the life to come, the happiness of
the just, the punishment of the wicked, and the sanctity of the social contract
and the laws. There you have the positive doctrines. As for the negative ones,
I limit them to one, intolerance, which is part of the cults we have excluded.
In my view, those
who distinguish between civil intolerance and theological intolerance are
making a mistake. These two forms of intolerance are inseparable. It is
impossible to live in peace with people one believes have been damned. To love them
would be to hate the God who is punishing them. It is imperative that we
convert them or persecute them. Wherever theological intolerance is permitted,
it is impossible for it not to have some civil effect, and as soon as it has, the sovereign is no longer sovereign, even in temporal
matters.101R From that point on, the
priests are the true masters. Kings are merely their officers.
Nowadays, when
there is no longer an exclusive national religion and when it is impossible to
have that any more, people should tolerate all religions which tolerate the others,
to the extent that their doctrines contain nothing which contradicts the duties
of the citizen. However, anyone who dares to say “Outside the Church there is
no salvation” should be driven from the state, unless the state is itself the
church and the prince is its pontiff. Such a doctrine is good only in a
theocratic government. In all others it is pernicious. The reason Henry IV is
said to have embraced the Roman religion should make every decent man leave it,
especially any prince who knew how to reason.
Now that I have set
down the true principles of political right and attempted to establish the
state on its foundation, I still have to strengthen it in its external
relations. This would include the rights of nations, trade,
the right of war and conquests, public right, leagues, negotiations, treaties,
and so on. But all that is a new subject, too vast for my limited vision, which
I should always have kept focussed on things closer to me.
End of the fourth and final part.
1[Rousseau’s note] “Scholarly studies into public
right are often merely histories of ancient abuses, and one is labouring in
vain when one takes the trouble to study them too much.” Manuscript
of A Treatise on the Interests of France in Relation to her Neighbours,
by the Marquis L. M. d’Argenson. That is precisely
what Grotius has done.
[Translator’s Note] Huge Grotius (1583-1645): an
eminent and extremely influential philosopher, who wrote extensively on international
and natural law. [Back to Text]
2[Translator’s note] Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679): an
English philosopher and author of Leviathan
(1651), a groundbreaking work on political philosophy. [Back to Text]
3[Translator’s note] Philo of Alexandria (c. 20
BC-c. 50) a Jewish philosopher, born in Egypt; Caligula (12-41): a Roman
emperor notorious for his cruelty and irrationality. [Back to Text]
4[Rousseau’s note] See Plutarch’s
short essay entitled That Animals Use
Reason. [Back to Text]
5[Translator’s note] The
three children of Saturn were Jupiter, Neptune, and Pluto (in Greek the father
was Cronos, and the children were Zeus, Poseidon, and
Hades). They divided up the world when Jupiter overthrew Saturn. Robinson
Crusoe, the hero of a novel by Daniel Defoe was shipwrecked on an island. [Back to Text]
6[Translator’s note] Francois Rabelais (1483-1553):
French monk, doctor, and writer, famous for his bawdy satires. [Back to Text]
7[Translator’s note]
The
Cyclops was a one-eyed monster who ate human flesh. The reference is to an episode
in Homer’s Odyssey where Odysseus are trapped in the Cyclops’ cave. [Back to Text]
8[Translator’s note] The Établissements of Louis IX
(1214-1270), king of France, complied around 1273, contains a set of ordinances
governing conduct at the court in Paris. The Peace of God was an attempt by the
Catholic Church (starting in the late tenth century) to limit private wars with
spiritual sanctions rather than by force. [Back to Text]
9[Translator’s note] Here the edition of 1782 adds
the following passage: “The Romans, who had a better understanding of and a
greater respect for the right of war than any nation on earth, carried their
scruples about this matter so far that they did not permit a citizen to serve
as a volunteer unless he had expressly committed himself against the enemy and
against a particular named enemy. When a legion in which Cato the Younger was doing
his first military service under Popilius was being decommissioned,
Cato the Elder wrote to Popilius that if he wanted
his son to continue to serve under him, he would have to make him swear a new
military oath, because, once his first oath was annulled, he could no longer
bear arms against the enemy. And the same Cato wrote to his son to take care to
present himself for combat only after he had sworn this new oath. I know that
one could counter my argument with the siege of Clusium
and other specific examples, but my concern is to cite laws and customs. The Romans
were those least likely to transgress their own laws, and they are the only
ones who have had such excellent legislation.” [Back to Text]
10[Rousseau’s note] The
true sense of this word has been almost entirely erased among modern people.
Most of them assume that a town is a city that and someone from a town is a
citizen. They do not understand that houses make a town but citizens create a
city. This same mistake cost the Carthaginians dearly in earlier days. I have
never read of the title citizens
being given to the subjects of any prince, not even in ancient times to the
Macedonians nor, in our own times, to the English, although they are closer to
liberty than anyone else. The French are the only ones who adopt this name of citizens with complete familiarity,
because they have no true idea of its meaning, as we can see from their
dictionaries. If they did, by usurping the word, they would be guilty of the
crime of treason [lèse-majesté]. With
them, this name expresses a virtue and not a right. When Bodin
wished to speak of our citizens and townspeople, he made a serious blunder in
taking one group for the other. M. d’Alembert did not make this mistake and in
his article Geneva clearly distinguished
the four orders of men (or even five, if one includes ordinary foreigners) who
live in our town, only two of which make up the republic. No other French author
I know of has understood the true meaning of the word citizens.
[Translator’s note] Jean Bodin
(1530-1596) was a French political writer, professor of law, and a member of
parliament. Jean-Baptiste d’Alembert
(1717-1783) was a French mathematician, philosopher, and one of the leading
intellectuals of the eighteenth century. [Back to Text]
11[Translator’s note] The
point here is that Rousseau’s notion of the state requires each citizen to be rationally
capable of understanding the social contract. This means that, while he may
well have a private interest different from the interest of the general will,
he understands why it is right that the interest of the general will prevail.
There is a danger, however, that individual citizens might not identify
themselves with such a rational person (who is a theoretical model) and would
thus avail themselves of the advantages of city life without being willing to
carry out their civic duties. [Back to Text]
12[Translator’s note] Nunez de Balboa ( c. 1475 to 1519), a Spanish explorer, was the first
European to lead an expedition to the Pacific (in 1513). [Back to Text]
13[Rousseau’s note] Under
bad governments this equality is only apparent and illusory. It serves merely
to keep the poor man destitute and the rich man in the place he has usurped. In
fact, laws are always useful to those who have possessions and harmful to those
who have nothing. Hence, it follows that the social state is advantageous to people
only to the extent that they all have something and that none of them has too
much. [Back to Text]
14[Rousseau’s note] In order for a will to be
general, it is not always necessary for it to be unanimous, but it is necessary
that all the votes be counted. Every formal exclusion
breaks the generality. [Back to Text]
15[Translator’s note] James II (1633-1701), the legitimate
king of England, was opposed by many powerful forces in the country (for various
reasons, especially his Roman Catholic faith). He was forced to leave the
country in 1688 in a bloodless coup. He was succeeded by William of Orange and
his wife Mary, who in 1689 became the joint sovereigns William III and Mary II.
[Back to Text]
16[Rousseau’s note] “Each interest,” states the
Marquis d’Argen-son, “has different principles. The
agreement of two particular interests is created by opposition to a third.” He
could have added that the agreement of all interests is created by opposition
to the interest of each individual. If there were no different interests, we
would hardly perceive the common interest, which would never encounter an obstacle.
Everything would proceed on its own, and politics
would cease to be an art. [Back to Text]
17[Rousseau’s note] “The truth is,” says Machiavelli,
“some divisions harm the republic, and others benefit it. When they are accompanied
by sects and partisan groups they are harmful, but those without sects and partisan
groups are advantageous. Since the founder of a republic cannot prevent the
emergence of enmities within it, he should at least stop them growing into
factions.” (History of Florence, Book
7).
[Translator’s note] Rousseau offers the above
quote from Machiavelli in Italian: Vera cosa è
. . . che alcune divisioni nuocono alle Republiche, e alcune giovano: quelle nuocono che sono dalle
sette e da partigiani accompagnate: qulle giovano che
seza sette, senza partigiani si mantengono. Non potendo adunque provedere un fondatore
d'una Republica che non siano nimicizie
in quella, hà da proveder almeno
che non vi siano sette.
[Translator’s note] Lycurgus (c. 820 BC-730 BC):
a legendary king of Sparta who established that state’s constitution; Solon (c. 638 BC-558 BC): an Athenian lawmaker; Numa (753 BC-673 BC): legendary second king of Rome; Servius (578 BC-535 BC): legendary sixth king of Rome. [Back to Text]
18[Rousseau’s note] Attentive readers, please do
not be in a hurry to accuse me of contradiction here. I was unable to avoid
that in my terms, given the poverty of the language. But wait. [Back to Text]
19[Translator’s note] The
phrase public entity is here used for
the French chose publique,
a literal translation of the Latin phrase res
publica, meaning a republic. [Back to Text]
20[Rousseau’s note] By
this word I do not mean merely an aristocracy or a democracy, but in general
every government guided by the general will, which is the law. To be legitimate,
the government does not have to be merged with the sovereign, but it has to be
the sovereign’s minister. In that case, even a monarchy is a republic. This
point will be explained in the book which follows. [Back to Text]
21[Rousseau’s note] A people does not become famous
except when its legislation begins to decline. We do not know for how many centuries
the institution of Lycurgus made the Spartans happy before it became something
the rest of Greece noticed. [Back to Text]
22[Translator’s note] Plato (428-348 BC): a major
philosopher of ancient Greece, whose Socratic dialogue The Statesman explores, among other things, the knowledge required
for political power; Montesquieu (1689-1755): a French political thinker. The
words by Montesquieu are not in italics or in quotation marks in Rousseau, although
they are an exact quotation. The reference is to his book Considerations on the Causes of the Grandeur and Decadence of the
Romans (1734). [Back to Text]
23[Rousseau’s note] People who think of Calvin merely
as a theologian have a poor grasp of the extent of his genius. The drafting of
our wise edicts, in which he played a major role, does him as much honour as
his Institutes. Whatever revolution
time may bring in our religion, so long as love of homeland and of liberty is
not extinguished among us, this great man’s memory will never cease to be a
blessing.
[Translator’s note] John Calvin (1509-1564): a
French theologian who played a formative role in the development of Protestantism
(his Institutes of the Christian Religion
was published in 1536) and who was a major figure in reforming the church and
the political system in Geneva. [Back to Text]
24[Translator’s note] The term decemvirs refers
to a committee of ten magistrates in the Roman Republic charged with drawing up
a code of laws. [Back to Text]
25[Rousseau’s note] “And in truth,” says Machiavelli,
“there has never been, among any people, an extraordinary codifier of laws who
did not have recourse to God, because without that his laws would not have been
accepted. For a prudent man is aware of many beneficial
things which do not, in themselves, contain clear reasons which make them capable
of convincing others.” Discourses
on Titus Livy, Book 1, Chapter 11.
[Translator’s note] Niccolo
Machiavelli (1469-1527): Italian diplomat, dramatist, and politician. Rousseau
quotes the Italian: E veramente, dit Machiavel, mai non fù alcuno ordinatore di leggi straordinarie
in un popolo, che non ricorresse a Dio, perche altrimenti non sarebbero accettate; perche sono molti
beni conosciuti da uno prudente,
i quali non hanno in se raggioni evidenti da potergli
persuadere ad altrui. [Back to Text]
26[Translator’s note] The
phrase “child of Ishmael” is a reference to Mohammed. [Back to Text]
27[Translator’s note] William Warburton
(1698-1779): an English cleric who, among other things, wrote on religious and
political subjects. [Back to Text]
28[Translator’s note] In the edition of 1782, this
sentence reads: “Most peoples, like men, . . .” [Back to Text]
29[Translator’s note] The Tarquins
were legendary kings of early Rome. According to tradition, they were
eventually overthrown, and the Roman Republic was established. The Dutch
Republic became independent in 1648, after many years of war against Spanish control.
Switzerland’s independence from the Holy Roman Empire was recognized in the
same year. [Back to Text]
30[Translator’s note] In
the edition of 1782, this sentence reads: “Youth is not infancy. For nations, as for men, there is a period of youth or, if you
will, of maturity. One must wait for this . . .” [Back to Text]
31[Translator’s note] Peter the Great (1672-1725):
Tsar of Russia, who presided over the expansion of the Russian Empire and widespread
reforms. [Back to Text]
32[Translator’s note] Rene Descartes (1596-1650):
French philosopher, whose mechanical theory of nature proposed that all matter
in space was swirling in vortices. [Back to Text]
33[Rousseau’s note] If there were two
neighbouring peoples and one could not do without the other,
the situation would be very difficult for the first and very dangerous for the
second. Every wise nation, in a similar case, will make a great effort to rid
the other of this dependency very quickly. The Republic of Tlaxcala, enclosed
within the Mexican empire, preferred to do without salt rather than to purchase
it from the Mexicans or even to accept it as a free gift. The wise people of
Tlaxcala saw the trap hidden beneath this generosity. They kept themselves
free, and this little state, confined inside that great empire, was finally the
instrument of its ruin. [Back to Text]
34[Translator’s note] Corsica won its independence
and declared itself a republic in 1755. [Back to Text]
35[Rousseau’s note] Do you wish then to provide
consistency to a state? Bring the two extremes together as much as possible. Do
not put up with rich people or beggars. These two conditions, by nature inseparable,
are equally fatal to the common good. From one come those who agitate for
tyranny and from the other come the tyrants. It is always between these two
that public liberty becomes a market commodity: one purchases it, and the other
sells it. [Back to Text]
36[Rousseau’s note] “Any branch of foreign
trade,” says the Marquis d’Argenson, “offers little
more than an apparent benefit to the kingdom in general. It can enrich some individuals
and even some towns, but the entire nation gains nothing from it, and the population
is no better off.” [Back to Text]
37[Translator’s note] The Spirit of the Laws (De L’esprit des lois):
a book on political theory written by Baron de Montesquieu, first published in
1748. [Back to Text]
38[Rousseau’s note] For
this reason, the College in Venice is called Most Serene Prince, even when the Doge is not in attendance. [Back to Text]
39[Translator’s note] A continued proportion is one
in which the second term in the first ratio, is the first term in the second:
e.g., A is to B as B is to C, or A/B = B/C.
See the next footnote for further details of Rousseau’s mathematical
analysis. [Back to Text]
40[Translator’s note] In the following paragraphs
Rousseau’s mathematical language may sound rather odd and, in places, confusing,
but his overall point is clear enough: in a properly ordered state the established
relationships among the people as subjects, the sovereign assembly of citizens,
and the government will vary depending upon the overall size of the population.
In the eighteenth century it was not uncommon for thinkers to subject moral and
political issues to mathematical analysis, often in a search for some precise
formula which would define the best political arrangement or course of action.
Rousseau himself sounds, at times, quite sceptical of
what he is doing here and, in fact, concludes his mathematical ruminations by,
in effect, dismissing them. To many readers, the analogies contribute little to
his argument, other than to emphasize that there is no one specific form of
government that will suit every state.
Briefly put, Rousseau’s
mathematical analysis goes something like this. There are three variables: the
total population, as the sovereign (S), the people as individual citizens (C),
and the government (G). He proposes that these should exist in a continued proportion,
so that S/G = G/C. (S and C are the extremes, and G is the mean proportion).
The value of C is always 1 (the individual citizen); therefore, the larger S becomes,
the larger G (the ‘middle term’) will have to be in order to maintain the proportion.
If we cross-multiply this equation, then S x 1 = G2 and G (the government)
is equal to the square root of S (the sovereign). In other words, the size of
the government should be the square root of the total population, a notion
which (we find out) Rousseau does not wish to reduce to a specific, easily
calculated number, in case that makes him look ridiculous. [Back to Text]
41[Translator’s note] This awkwardly worded sentence
seems to mean that with the ratio of the sovereign to the citizen (S/C), if the
population grows, from a mathematic point of view the fraction gets larger:
since C is always equal to 1, any increase in S (the quotient) will increase
the value of the total ratio. However, from the point of view of the individual
citizen, the larger S becomes the smaller his share in the sovereignty, and
thus the more his fraction of rule decreases. [Back to Text]
42[Translator’s note]
The phrase “double ratio” is somewhat confusing.
It seems to refer to the product of the two simple ratios (S/G and G/C). If we
multiply these together and remember that C = 1, the product is SG/GC which
factors down to S. Thus if the double ratio increases or decreases, S increases
or decreases correspondingly. To maintain the equality of the two simple
ratios, the middle term (G) will have to change. For all the potentially
confusing mathematical language, Rousseau’s point is simple enough: changes in
the size of the total population should result in a corresponding change in the
size of the government (“the middle term”). [Back to Text]
43[Rousseau’s note] The Palatine of Posen, father
of the King of Poland, Duke of Lorraine. [Back to Text]
44[Rousseau’s note] It is clear that the word Optimates among
the ancients did not mean the best but the most powerful. [Back to Text]
45[Rousseau’s note] It is particularly important
to have laws regulating the way magistrates are elected, for in leaving that to
the will of the prince, one cannot avoid falling into a hereditary aristocracy,
as has happened to the republics of Venice and Berne. Thus, the former has for
a long time been in a state of dissolution, but the latter has maintained
itself thanks to the extreme wisdom of its senate. It is a very honourable and
very dangerous exception. [Back to Text]
46[Translator’s note] The
following passage was added to the edition of 1782: “Machiavelli was an honorable
man and a good citizen, but he was attached to the House of Medici, and so, when
his homeland was oppressed, he was forced to disguise his love of liberty. The
choice of his detestable hero in itself demonstrates well enough his secret intention,
and the contradiction between the principles in his book The Prince and those in his Discourses
on Livy and in his History of
Florence shows that this profound political thinker has so far had only
superficial or corrupt readers. The court in Rome has strictly prohibited his
book. I can well believe it, for that is the court he portrays most clearly.”
The “detestable hero” referred to in the quotation is Cesare
Borgia, a notoriously corrupt and ultimately unsuccessful politician, whom
Machiavelli repeated praises in The
Prince. [Back to Text]
47[Translator’s note] Dionysius the Younger, or
Dionysius II (c. 397 BC – 343 BC): king of Syracuse, famous for his dissolute
lifestyle. [Back to Text]
48[Rousseau’s note] Tacitus, Histories, Book I. [Translator’s
note] Rousseau quotes the Latin: Nam utilissimus idem ac brevissiumus bonarum malarumque rerum delectus, cogitare quid aut nolueris sub alio principe, aut
volueris. [Back to Text]
49[Rousseau’s note] In The Statesman. [Back to Text]
50[Translator’s note] Jean Chardin
(1643-1713), a French traveller, who wrote about his travel in Persia and the
Near East. [Back to Text]
51[Translator’s note] Posillipo
is an area in Naples. [Back to Text]
52[Rousseau’s note] This does not
contradict what I said above in Book 2, Chapter 9 about the disadvantages of
large states. For there the issue was the authority of the government over its
members, and here the issue is its power against the subjects. The government’s
scattered members serve as pressure points for acting on the people from a
distance, but it has no pressure point for acting directly on its members
themselves. Thus, in one of these cases, the length of the lever is a source of
its weakness, and in the other a source of its power. [Back to Text]
53[Rousseau’s note] We
should use the same principle to judge those ages which deserve pride of place
for the prosperity of the human race. We have admired excessively those periods
where arts and letters have flourished, without penetrating the secret object
of their culture or without considering its fatal effects. What was part of slavery, ignorant people called humanity. Will we
never see in the maxims of books the crude self-interest which prompts the authors to speak out? No, for no matter
what they can say, when a country, despite its brilliance, has a declining population,
it is not true that all is going well, and the fact that a poet has an income
of one hundred thousand livres is not enough to make
his age the finest of all. We need to examine, not so much the apparent calm
and the tranquillity of the leaders, but the wellbeing of entire nations, and above all of the most highly populated states.
A hailstorm desolates a few cantons, but it rarely leads to famine. Riots and
civil wars make leaders very afraid, but they do not cause genuine disasters
for the people, who can even get some relief during a dispute over who will be
their tyrants. Their real prosperity or calamity arises from their permanent
condition. When everything remains crushed under the yoke, that is when everything
declines; that is when their leaders destroy them at will: Where they make a desert, they call it peace. When the bickering
among our great men disturbed the kingdom of France and the Coadjutor of Paris
carried a knife in his pocket into parliament, that
did not prevent large numbers of French people from prospering in dignity, freedom,
and comfort. In earlier days, Greece flourished in the midst of the most savage
wars: there were rivers of blood, and yet the entire country was covered with
people. It would seem, says Machiavelli, that in the
midst of murders, proscriptions, and civil wars, our republic became stronger.
The virtue of its citizens, their morality, and their independence did more to
strengthen it than all the quarrels did to weaken it. A little agitation makes
spirits resilient, and what truly makes the species prosper is not so much
peace as liberty.
[Translator’s note] Rousseau quotes the Latin: Idque apud imperitos humanitas vocabatur, cum pars servitutis essent; and ubi solitudinem faciunt, pacem appellant. [Back to Text]
54[Rousseau’s note] The slow formation and the
progress of the Republic of Venice in its lagoons offers a notable example of
this succession, and it is truly astonishing that over a period of more than
twelve hundred years the Venetians seem to be still only at the second stage,
which began with the Serrar di Consiglio in 1198. As far as concerns the ancient
dukes, for whom the Venetians are criticized, it has been established, no
matter what the Scrutiny of Venetian
Liberty [Squitino
della liberta
Veneta] may say about them, that they were not
their sovereigns.
People will not fail to raise
the Roman Republic as an objection to what I say. They will claim that it followed
a completely opposite development, passing from monarchy to aristocracy and
from aristocracy to democracy. I am a long way from sharing such an opinion.
What Romulus first established
was a mixed government, which quickly degenerated into despotism. For
particular reasons that state died before its time, the way one sees a newborn
die before reaching adulthood. The expulsion of the Tarquins
was the true age of the birth of the Roman Republic. But at first it did not
take on a constant form, because, by not abolishing the class of patricians, it
carried out only half its work. For in this way, a hereditary aristocracy,
which is the worst form of legitimate administration, remained in conflict with
democracy, and so the form of the government, always uncertain and fluid, was
not fixed until the establishment of the tribunes, as Machiavelli has
demonstrated. Only then was there a true government
and a genuine democracy. At that time, the populace was, in fact, not merely
sovereign but also magistrate and judge. The senate was only a subordinate
tribunal to moderate or concentrate the government. The
consuls themselves, although patricians, chief magistrates, and absolute
generals in war, were in Rome merely presidents of the people.
From that point on, the
government, too, evidently followed its natural tendency and inclined strongly
to aristocracy. Once the group of patricians, as it were, abolished itself on
its own, the aristocracy was no longer confined to the body of patricians, as
it is in Venice and Genoa, but in the body of the senate was made up of
patricians and plebeians, even in the body of tribunes when they began to usurp
active power. For words have no effect on things, and when the populace has
leaders who govern on its behalf, no matter what name these leaders bear, the
government is always an aristocracy.
The abuses of the aristocracy
gave rise to the civil wars and the triumvirate. Sulla, Julius Caesar, and Augustus
became, in fact, veritable monarchs, and finally, under the despotism of Tiberius,
the state was dissolved. The history of Rome, therefore, does not contradict my
principle but confirms it.
[Translator’s note] The Serrar di Consiglio (Closing of the Council) refers to the
decision to limit membership on the ruling council in Venice to a small group,
an action which, in effect, created a hereditary aristocracy. This took place
later than Rousseau indicates (in 1297 rather than 1198). Squitino della liberta Veneta, published in 1612, attacked the traditional notion
of Venetian liberty and argued that Venice had been subject to German emperors.
The Tribunes were elected Roman officials representing the people. The office
was established in 494 BC, in response to a political crisis. The First
Triumvirate was a private power-sharing agreement among Pompey (106-48 BC),
Julius Caesar (100-44 BC), and Marcus Licinius
(115-53 BC). Sulla (c. 138-78 BC) established himself as a dictator at Rome.
Augustus (63 BC-AD 14) emerged as the winner in the civil wars and became
Rome’s first emperor; Tiberius (42 BC-AD 37) was his successor. [Back to Text]
55[Rousseau’s note] “For all those are considered
and called tyrants who wield perpetual power in a state which is accustomed to
liberty” Cornelius Nepos in Life of Miltiades. It is true that Aristotle
in the Nicomachean Ethics, Book 8, Chapter 10, makes a distinction
between a tyrant and a king, in that the former governs to benefit himself and the latter only to benefit his subjects. But
apart from the fact that generally all the Greek writers took the world tyrant in another sense, as is most apparent
in the Hieron
of Xenophon, it would follow from Aristotle’s distinction that since the
beginning of the world there has not yet been a single king.
[Translator’s note] Rousseau quotes Nepos in
Latin: Omnes enim et habentur et dicuntur
tyranni, qui potestate utuntur perpetua in ea civitate quae libertate usa est. Nepos was a Roman historian (c. 110 BC–c. 25
BC). Xenophon (c. 430 BC–354 BC) was a Greek writer who wrote a dialogue featuring
Hiero, a tyrant of Syracuse. [Back to Text]
56[Translator’s note] The Great King was a common
title for the king of Persia. Alliances of Greek cities twice defeated Persian
invasions (in 490 BC and 480 BC). [Back to Text]
57[Rousseau’s note] In almost
the sense of the word speaker in the
English parliament. The similarity of these offices would have led to conflict
between the consuls and the tribunes, even if all jurisdictions had been suspended.
[Translator’s note] In Rome the comitia were popular assemblies. Rousseau
discusses them in detail in Book 4. The tribunes were leaders of the people
(rather than the upper classes). [Back to Text]
58[Translator’s note] The Gracchi were two brothers
in the second century BC who led efforts for land reforms to benefit the
people. They were both assassinated. [Back to Text]
59[Translator’s note] Lictors
were Roman citizens selected to protect the more important public officials. [Back to Text]
60[Rousseau’s note] To
adopt in cold countries the luxury and softness of the Orientals is to wish to
give oneself their chains. It is to submit to those chains even more unavoidably
than they do. [Back to Text]
61[Rousseau’s note] That is what I had proposed
to do in the sequel to this work, when, in dealing with external relations, I
would have come to confederations, a completely new subject whose principles
have yet to be established. [Back to Text]
62[Translator’s note] This
process is still standard procedure in meetings run on parliamentary principles
or under Robert’s Rules of Order. It is
called “moving into Committee of the Whole.” The procedure permits discussions
which are not bound by the stricter rules of the regular meeting or legislative
session. [Back to Text]
63[Translator’s note] Rousseau uses the term cas odieux (literally
odious cases), here translated as
“potentially dangerous cases.” According to Christopher Betts, the French
phrase is an old legal term “denoting a case in which the exercise of a right,
if permitted, would be harmful in some way.” [Back to Text]
64[Translator’s note] The comitia in ancient Republican Rome were
the legal assemblies of the people. The decemvirs, as noted earlier, were members of a commission
(originally set up in ancient Rome in 452 BC) entrusted to create a code of
law. [Back to Text]
65[Rousseau’s note] On the condition, of course,
that he does not leave in order to evade his duty and to avoid serving his homeland
at a time when she has need of us. Escaping then would be a criminal and
punishable act. It would no longer be a departure, but desertion. [Back to Text]
66[Translator’s note] The
phrase “sent to the bells” refers to the fact that in Berne, those sentenced to
hard labour had bells hung around their necks. It is not clear what punishment
is meant by à la discipline. Oliver
Cromwell (1599-1658): leader of the parliamentary forces in the English Civil
War, who led a successful rebellion against Charles I, executed the king, and
became Lord Protector; Duke of Beaufort (Francois de Vendome) (1616-1669):
important French political figure who joined the insurrection against royal
power (the Fronde). [Back to Text]
67[Translator’s note] Publius
Cornelius Tacitus (56 AD-117): historian of the Roman emperors; Marcus Salvius Otho (32-69): a Roman emperor;
Aulus Vitellius Germanicus (15-69): Roman emperor, who succeeded Otho. [Back to Text]
68[Rousseau’s note] This
should always be understood as applying to a free state. For in other places,
family, possessions, lack of shelter, necessity, and violence can keep a resident
in the country in spite of himself. In that case, his remaining there, in
itself, no longer presupposes consent to or violation of the contract. [Back to Text]
69[Rousseau’s note] In Genoa, one can read the
word Libertas
[Liberty] on the front of prisons and
on the chains of the galley slaves. This use of the motto is good and just. In
fact, it is only the malefactors of all stations who prevent the citizen from being
free. In a country where all such people were in the galleys, one would enjoy
the most perfect freedom. [Back to Text]
70[Translator’s note] The Doge was the leader of the Venetian Republic, elected for life from
among the aristocratic Venetians. The Barnabites were
impoverished nobles who had a right to attend the Grand Council, the governing
assembly in Venice. [Back to Text]
71[Translator’s note] Abbé de Saint-Pierre
(1658-1743): French writer, who, among other things, proposed certain reforms
of Louis XIV’s administration. [Back to Text]
72[Rousseau’s note] The
name Rome, which people claim comes
from Romulus, is Greek and signifies force. The name Numa is also Greek and signifies law. How likely is it that the first two
kings of this town would have had in advance names so well related to what they
achieved? [Back to Text]
73[Translator’s note] Servius Tullius (who reigned from 578-535 BC): legendary sixth king
of Rome. [Back to Text]
74[Translator’s note] Marcus Terentius
Varro (116–27 BC): Roman writer; Pliny (the Elder) (23-79) Roman writer and
natural philosopher; Appius Claudius (c. 500 BC): a
Sabine who favoured peace with Rome and who moved with his followers to the
city. [Back to Text]
75[Translator’s note] The
censors were public officials in charge of the census and public morality. [Back to Text]
76[Translator’s note] Field of Mars (Campus Martius): a large open area in Rome,
used for military training and displays. [Back to Text]
77[Translator’s note] Gaius Marius (157-86 BC):
Roman general who reorganized Rome’s military forces and served as consul
(i.e., head of the government) seven times.
[Back to Text]
78[Rousseau’s note] I say on the Field of Mars, because it was there that the comitia by centuries assembled. In the
two other arrangements, the people gathered at
the forum or elsewhere, and on those occasions the capite censi had as much influence and authority
as the foremost citizens. [Back to Text]
79[Translator’s note] The tribunes were officials
elected by the plebs (common people) to represent them. They had no official
powers but, because no one was allowed to harm them (i.e., they were
sacrosanct), they exercised considerable political influence. [Back to Text]
80[Translator’s note] A curule
magistrate in Rome was a senior official entitled to use a special chair (the sella curulis). [Back to Text]
81[Rousseau’s note] The century chosen by lot in
this manner was called praerogativa,
because it was the first one asked for its vote, and from this practice the
word prerogative is derived. [Back to Text]
82[Rousseau’s note] Supervisors, distributors of
the ballots, and collectors of votes. [Translator’s note] Rousseau uses Latin terms: Custodes, Diribitores, Rogatores suffragiorum. [Back to Text]
83[Translator’s note] The ephors were elected senior officials in ancient Sparta who
played a major role in running the state. [Back to Text]
84[Translator’s note] Agis (265–241 BC): king
of Sparta, who tried to correct political abuses; Cleomenes:
king of Sparta (235-222 BC). [Back to Text]
85[Rousseau’s note] This
nomination was made at night and in secret, as if they were ashamed to set a
man above the laws. [Back to Text]
86[Translator’s note] The
consuls were the most important political figures in the Roman Republic. Two
were elected each year. Alba was a legendary king of Rome. [Back to Text]
87[Translator’s note] Lucius
Cornelius Sulla (138-78 BC): a Roman general and politician, who marched on
Rome, defeated Gaius Marius (157–86 BC), who was defending the city, and established
himself as a dictator; Gnaeus Pompeius
(106–48 BC), an important political and military leader in Rome, who in 49 BC refused
to defend the city against the advance of Julius Caesar (100–44 BC) and his
army. [Back to Text]
88[Translator’s note] Lucius Sergius Catilina (108–62 BC): a Roman
senator who attempted conspiratorial revolts against the Roman Republic, after
the second of which (in 63 BC) he fled from Rome. [Back to Text]
89[Rousseau’s note] This point Cicero could not
have been sure about if he had proposed a dictator, for he did not dare nominate
himself, and he could not be sure that his colleague would nominate him. [Back to Text]
90[Translator’s note] Marcus Tullius
Cicero (106–43 BC): a major Roman writer, orator, and politician, elected
Consul in 63 BC, exiled after his success in the Catiline affair (for executing
Roman citizens illegally) and then permitted to return. [Back to Text]
91[Rousseau’s note] In
this chapter I am merely pointing out something I have dealt with at greater
length in the Letter to M. d’Alembert.
[Back to Text]
92[Translator’s note] In
the 1782 edition, Rousseau adds: “They were from a different island which the refined
nature of our language does not permit me to name on this occasion.” [Back to Text]
93[Rousseau’s note] “Nonne ea quae possidet Chamos Deus tuus tibi jure debentur?” Such is the text
of the Vulgate. Father de Carrieres has translated
it: “Do you not believe you have the right to possess what belongs to Chamos, your god?” I do not know the force of the Hebrew
text, but I see that in the Vulgate Jephthah
positively recognizes the right of the god Chamos and
that the French translator has weakened this acknowledgement by adding “according to you,” which is not in the
Latin. [Back to Text]
94[Rousseau’s note] It is perfectly clear that
the Phocian War, which was called the Sacred War, was
not a war about religion. Its purpose was to punish sacrilegious actions, not
to subdue non-believers. [Back to Text]
95[Rousseau’s note] One should take careful note
that what binds the clergy together into a body is not so much formal assemblies,
like those in France, as the communion of churches. Communion and excommunication
are for the clergy the social pact with which it ensures that it will always be
the master of peoples and kings. All the priests in the communion together are
fellow citizens, even if they are at opposite ends of the earth. This invention
is a political masterpiece. There was nothing like it among the pagan priests, and that is why they never formed a corporate body
of clergy.
[Translator’s note] Thomas Hobbes (1588 -1679):
an English philosopher whose masterpiece of political theory Leviathan was published in 1651. [Back to Text]
96[Rousseau’s note] Among
other things in a letter of Grotius to his brother (April 11, 1643) notice what
this learned man agrees with and what he criticizes in the book de Cive. It is
true that, with his tendency to be indulgent, he appears to forgive what the
author has done well for the sake of what he has done badly, but not everyone
is so merciful. [Back to Text]
97[Translator’s note] Pierre Bayle (1647-1706): a
French philosopher who advocated a separation between organized religion and
the state; William Warburton (1698-1779): English writer and bishop who, among
many other endeavours, wrote about the importance of an alliance between church
and state. [Back to Text]
98[Translator’s note] Sacer estod [Be accursed]:
an ancient Roman formal sentence of punishment. [Back to Text]
99[Rousseau’s note] “In the republic,” says the
Marquis d’Argenson, “each person is perfectly free in
what is not harmful to others.” There you have the invariable limit. One cannot
state the matter more precisely. I could not deny myself the pleasure of
quoting this manuscript from time to time, although it is unknown to the
public, in honour of the memory of an illustrious and respectable man, who even
in ministerial office maintained the heart of a true citizen as well as just
and sound views on the government of his country. [Back to Text]
100[Rousseau’s note] When Julius Caesar was
pleading for Catiline, he tried to establish the
doctrine of the mortality of the soul. Cato and Cicero, in their refutation of
him, did not waste time philosophizing. They were content to show that Caesar
spoke like a bad citizen and was advancing a doctrine pernicious to the state.
And this, in fact, was what the Roman senate had to judge, not a question of
theology. [Back to Text]
101[Rousseau’s note] Marriage, for example, is a
civil contract and thus has civil consequences without which it is impossible
for society even to survive. Suppose, then, that the clergy succeeded in claiming
the sole right to permit this act, a right which it must necessarily usurp in
every intolerant religion. In that case, is it not obvious that validating the
authority of the church in this matter will make the authority of the prince
ineffectual, for he will then have only as many subjects as those the clergy
will be willing to provide him? If the church has the power to marry or not to
marry people depending on whether or not they profess this or that doctrine, on
whether they accept or reject this or that formula, or on whether they are more
or less devout, is it not obvious that, by behaving prudently and holding firm,
it alone will administer inheritances, offices, citizens, and even the state,
which could not survive if were composed of nothing but bastards? But, it will
be said, people will appeal on the grounds of abuse, there will be summonses
and decrees, and temporal goods will be seized. How pitiful! The clergy, given
that it has a little—I will not say courage—but good sense, will let this
happen and go on its way. It will calmly permit these appeals, summonses,
decrees, and seizures and will end up by remaining in control. There is no
great sacrifice, it seems to me, in abandoning a
portion when one is sure of securing all. [Back to Text]
[Back
to johnstonia Home Page]
Page loads on johnstonia web
files
20,451,618
View Stats