Why Should I Obey the State?
[The following is the text of a lecture given to a Grade XII class
in Cowichan High School, Duncan, BC, by Ian Johnston of Malaspina University-College, Nanaimo, BC, in September
2003. The text is in the public domain and may be used by anyone, in whole or
in part, without permission and without charge, provided the source is
acknowledged—released September 2003]
I’m here today to provide, as best I can in a very short time, a
grand large-scale map of some of the complex territory you will be exploring in
more detail in your studies of some very important political thinkers, whose
books established much of the theoretical basis for our understanding and
discussions of modern politics. This task requires that I move very quickly
through some complicated issues and sophisticated theories, so inevitably these
remarks will be very cursory. However, if I can set up some useful signposts
along the way that will help you in your more detailed explorations, then I
will have succeeded in what I set out to do.
SOME PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS
Let’s begin with a really fundamental question about what we call
a state or a country—the basic political unit your studies are concerned with.
What is its purpose? What is this political organization supposed to provide
its citizens? Well, at the most basic level, the state has only two major
functions. The first is to protect its citizens from outside interference and
oppression—that is, the state has to defend its independence and freedom to
govern itself (otherwise it ceases to be a state and becomes a province in
someone else’s empire). And the second is to establish and protect justice
within the state. Justice here does not mean simply a judicial system but
something much more all-encompassing—a sense of fair allocation of the
resources of the state, a idea derived from the Greek idea of justice as an “arrangement,”
the proper distribution of economic, cultural, educational, and judicial
services carried on in the community (the words fair and proper here,
as we shall see, do not necessarily mean equal).
In order to carry out these two functions the state has at its
disposal considerable power—physical power (in the form of police, judges, and
soldiers), economic power, cultural power (including, most importantly,
religion), and social power (especially public opinion). And so the central
issue of politics—the issue that, in one way or another, almost all important political
theorists are seeking to address—becomes an attempt to answer this question:
What is the best way to organize the power in the state in order to achieve the
two goals of the state, freedom and justice? To whom should we entrust the
power at the state’s disposal in order to achieve these goals? Who should rule,
and who should obey, and how do we define, describe, and justify the relationship
between them?
Any attempt to answer such questions requires a theoretical defense
of the particular model being proposed, a comprehensive account which provides
the citizens with an understanding of why a particular distribution of power
and decision making is justified, is legitimate. Such an account will then
become an integral part of the way the state educates its young and persuades
its citizens to comply with the arrangements. In other words, such an answer
will have to provide a satisfactory and effective answer to the most basic
question in political science, “Why should I obey the state?” An answer of some
kind must be available to the citizens, since they have to put up all the time
with state decisions which affect them and which often require them to do
things they might not wish to do (like pay taxes). Unless most of them willingly
obey most of the time, running the state may well become unworkable.
[Parenthetically, one might wonder just how a state would fare
without such a theoretical justification, without a persuasive framework for
establishing the legitimacy of the distribution of power. In such a situation,
it would seem that the only way the rulers could justify the arrangement is by
an appeal to force—obey or you’ll be seriously hurt. While this answer is
obviously part of any political system, if it is the only basis
for the authority of the rulers, then in a very real way the state has no
identity, no coherent sense of itself, and will last only as long as the
present power arrangements hold (which is why even the most tyrannical regimes
often go to great lengths, as in the case of, say, Nazi Germany or modern North
Korea, to legitimize themselves with the cult of a particular leader or
ideology of race or religion or sham elections.]
THE OLD ORDER
All of the political thinkers you are studying are addressing this
question. In fact, they largely define the various major alternatives which
characterize modern political life in the West. But before turning directly to
these thinkers, let me pose this question: Why is it that in the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries political theory was such a hot
topic? What happened that suddenly prompted such energetic and long-lasting
public debate about the nature of the state? Given that major intellectual
movements always arise in response to some previous arrangements, usually in
cases where those arrangements have become problematic, we might well want
initially to explore what crisis these writers were addressing in their concerted
efforts to propose new political models.
To answer this point, I need to say a few necessarily superficial
remarks about what I’ll call the Old Order, the political arrangements which
had governed Europe for centuries and which, for reasons I’ll mention in a
moment, had become a problem. The Old Order was, briefly put, a political
organization of the state based on inherited rank, in which society consisted
of a carefully graded hierarchy of value—the king and the major aristocracy and
bishops at the top and the peasants at the bottom, with various degrees in
between. One’s position on the scale was determined, almost without exception,
by one’s birth and the traditions of one’s community (one’s social position was
not something one could choose or, in almost all cases, earn; it was something
set by the position into which one was born). Movement up and down the scale
was extraordinarily difficult and certainly not encouraged. The distribution of
power in the state corresponded to the scale: the higher one’s position, the
greater one’s power. And with power came responsibility for those one ruled,
with the absence of power came the obligation to obey.
One’s position in the hierarchy determined precisely the nature of one’s
responsibilities and obligations.
What held this system together was a network of personal relationships
among the rulers and the governed. Political life was
overwhelmingly local, since the vast majority of people lived in very small and
traditional agricultural communities where their families had lived for generations
and where the power base (the ownership of land and the religious authority)
had not changed for centuries. The theoretical basis for this arrangement was
twofold—the first was an appeal to traditions, “You should obey the state
because that’s what we’ve always done around here.” The second was an appeal to
religion—the hierarchical structure of the state was part of the natural order
ordained by God (which manifested itself in the organization of the entire
universe)—who had arranged things in this way so that the wiser and better
people governed the less capable: “You should obey the state because that’s God’s
will.” In such a system, justice and freedom in the state depended upon virtue
in the rulers—because they were more virtuous than others, they knew best how
to use power for the right purposes. And so in the centuries before the
challenges to the Old Order began, the central issue in a great deal of
political writing was this: How do we encourage virtue in the rulers? For if we
have that, then justice and freedom are more secure.
The Old Order lasted as an effective political organization for
centuries and established the foundations for what we now call Western Europe.
There were always inherent tensions within it, of course, particularly dynastic
squabbles among the aristocracy about the legitimacy of succession (e.g., the
Wars of the Roses), about control of particular territories (e.g., the Hundred
Years’ War), about the appropriate balance of secular and religious authority,
and about particular power arrangements with the elite (clashes between kings
and senior barons, for example), among other things, but there was no
significant major argument about the nature of the state and the justification
for it. In that sense, it was a spectacularly successful and long-lasting
political model.
The challenge to the Old Order arose gradually out of at least
three major conditions. The first (in no particular order) was the rising power
of capitalism in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, which created,
through trade, an increasing number of people with growing economic power but
relatively little political clout. The Old Order’s structure of inherited power
put the ruling authority for the most part squarely in the hands of those
traditional aristocratic families or institutions which owned land and derived
their wealth from the land. Its very conservative
traditions had no room for allocating significant power to the rising group of
wealthy business people (whose activities were enormously energized by the
exploration and exploitation of the Americas). This new business class began
making demands for political power commensurate with its economic power,
demands which the Old Order tended to resist. Hence arose
a conflict that led ultimately to the English Civil War and the American War of
Independence (both prompted, in large part, by what the business groups saw as
taxation without satisfactory political representation).
The second factor was what seemed to be the deplorable and growing
lack of politically effective virtue in the rulers, which in some places
(especially in Italy and later in France) seemed incapable of promoting
domestic peace and economic prosperity. The growing power of some royal
families often encouraged them to engage in disastrous and inconclusive wars of
expansion or economically wasteful attempts to celebrate the glory and power of
the king, to the detriment of many citizens, particularly the poor (the
architectural achievements of Louis XIV, for example, from Louisburg to
Versailles are an eloquent testimony of this tendency, to say nothing of his frequently
catastrophic and economically crippling military and colonizing expeditions).
Perhaps the most decisive factor, however, was the loss of religious
uniformity, and the religious wars which followed (in the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries), for this put into question the very heart of the Old
Order, the nature of virtue itself. Once people could no longer agree about
that and were prepared to defy their rulers or kill their fellow citizens over
competing definitions of virtue in the name of the one true religion, the
fabric of the Old Order was ripped apart. I’m not sure if you like to jot down
important dates or not, but if you do, then one you might like to commit to
memory is 1648, the year the Thirty Years’ War ended, a conflict in which for
the first and last time virtually all of Western Europe tore itself apart over
religious questions, the various parties seeking, quite literally, to exterminate
other faiths. When that war ended inconclusively, it was clear to many people
that European states needed a new framework for political life. All of the
writers you are studying are responding to this need.
One might include in the list another key factor in the gradual
collapse of the Old Order—an astonishing explosion in the population in the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, accompanied by a rapid population shift
from small agricultural communities into huge new cities. This development
(whose causes historians are still debating) destroyed
the fundamental political unit of the Old Order, the small traditional
community with a clear geographical identity and strongly shared communal
traditions.
I don’t want to suggest with this list that the transformation of
the Old Order happened immediately. That was, for the most part, a slow
process (although there were significant major explosions along the way, like
the English Civil War, the American War of Independence, and the French
Revolution). Nor do I want to claim in the remarks which follow that
these political thinkers necessarily had an immediate and revolutionary impact.
What makes their work so important is that they provided those people who were
seeking changes in the Old Order alternative models and a different vocabulary,
so that reformist and revolutionary movements could establish a concerted program
of action. It’s important to remember here that the most important
thinkers are generally those who redefine the conversation,
who put on the table new ways of thinking about old problems, and who thus help
to channel the energies of others in new directions. Such thinkers are
not necessarily themselves revolutionary activists (although some are), nor do
their theories always have an immediately revolutionary impact.
A SHORT DIGRESSION: MACHIAVELLI
Machiavelli, who is often hailed as the first modern voice in political
theory, pre-dates the Reformation, of course, and so his famous book The
Prince (written in 1513) is more an anticipation of what was to come
later. He is writing in direct response to the political anarchy in Italy, long
characterized by what seemed never-ending and very bloody wars between the
various rival ducal and papal states.
What makes Machiavelli interesting is not any comprehensive new
theory of the state (which he does not offer) but his revolutionary insistence
that the traditional emphasis on virtue in the ruler is a mistake. What the
ruler should concentrate on is not doing the right thing but doing whatever is
effective for protecting and ensuring his own power. And that necessarily requires
that the ruler abandon any notion of adhering to virtue. He should lie,
torture, kill, assassinate, invade, and so on as the situation requires. What
Machiavelli recommends, above all, is an intelligent practical sense of what
particular actions will work best in a given situation to make the ruler’s
power more secure, combined with a ruthless willingness to undertake such
action (such a quality Machiavelli calls virtu—hence
the old saying about him, “There is no virtue in virtu”)
. Machiavelli argues that this is, in fact, how successful rulers have always
operated, and therefore this is how the modern prince ought to proceed. In his
political world the end (protecting and increasing the prince’s power) always
justifies the means. In modern times this attitude is often called Realpolitik.
Reactions to Machiavelli have typically fallen into one of three
camps. Many (including most of his contemporaries) dismiss his proposals as
morally absurd and, as often as not, politically self-defeating. Machiavelli’s
prescriptions, many argue, are a recipe for evil actions and for political
catastrophe (a good contemporary example is the US-UK position on Iraq. Having,
in effect, lied to justify a war they wanted to fight, the political leaders of
those countries are now in a position of having to beg for help from those who
refused to believe them and of having, with increasing desperation, to tell
their own citizens that the enormous and continuing cost in lives and dollars
is worth it. Moreover, their Machiavellian tactics may have seriously
weakened the power of both leaders and, of course, diverted resources away from
the war against terrorism).
Defenders of Machiavelli argue that he is right to see that politics
has to be based upon the way people really behave and not how we might like
them to be. Since the essential prerequisite for a political life is stability,
Machiavelli correctly insists that the prince must be prepared to make sure his
power is secure at all costs—and for that he has to be willing to use the full
range of options without moral restraint. Only that will guarantee the security
of the state upon which everything else depends.
A third group sees Machiavelli’s political vision as a satire, a
work ridiculing those very things for which defenders of Machiavelli as a
serious political thinker applaud him. There’s no time to review this position
here; those interested in seeing why one could look at the book in this light
might like to read another lecture of mine available through this link—Machiavelli.
THOMAS HOBBES
The first and most important response to the deficiencies of the
Old Order was the work of Thomas Hobbes in the second half of the seventeenth
century, immediately following the Thirty Years’ War and the English Civil War.
Though by no means accepted immediately, Hobbes’ radical new vision (in his
book The Leviathan) established the theoretical foundations of
modern liberal states, including our own (which owes more to his vision of
politics than to the views of any other thinker).
Like Machiavelli, Hobbes begins with the recognition that virtue
is an insufficient basis for justice in the modern state. He admires virtue but
acknowledges that there’s not enough of it around, because human beings by
nature are greedy, fearful, jealous, and quarrelsome creatures. The only way
they can live peacefully together is if they agree to submit themselves
completely to a sovereign power which will have the authority to make laws and
enforce them equally on all the citizens. Hobbes doesn’t define a particular
version of the sovereign—he prefers monarchy, but what he has to offer works
equally well with an assembly of delegates, like a parliament, or any other
form of governing authority on which people can agree.
Hobbes thus proposes a radically new model of the state: a single
all-powerful sovereign and a general population all equally obligated to obey
the sovereign’s written laws, which are the only recognized authority people
have to acknowledge. Old traditions, inherited customs, traditional religious
attitudes, long-standing personal relationships, old systems of rank and
privilege—none of these matters unless the sovereign’s law makes them matter.
Our only obligation as citizens is to the sovereign’s law. In an all-important
sentence, Hobbes lays down one of most important liberal principles: What is
not forbidden by the sovereign’s law is allowed (more about this in a minute).
Hobbes justifies this arrangement with a very interesting argument,
too complex to describe in detail here. But let me offer a few highlights.
Essentially he invites us into a thought experiment designed to show us that
his model is the reasonable thing to agree with (given what human beings are
like) and that it’s in our self-interest to follow his recommendations. We should
obey the state, Hobbes argues, not because it’s established by God (it clearly
is not), but because it serves our self-interest to do so.
Hobbes begins by picturing what human beings are like without
political organizations—in what he calls a state of nature. Here everyone is perfectly
free—there are no laws and no morality (since for Hobbes morality is
ineffective without laws and a sword to back them up)—and each person has the
right to grab and keep whatever he can for as long as he can. This leads, in
Hobbes’ most quoted phrase, to a life that is “nasty, brutish, and short,” a
condition which sooner or later persuades people that they should submit to a
common authority so that they can get some peace and quiet to enjoy their lives
free of a constant fear of death. In effect, a group of free individuals agrees
to submit to the unconditional authority of some outside party (a king or
sovereign assembly) who will protect them from each other. It’s important to
note that in Hobbes’ theory the sovereign is not a party to the contract (which
exists among those governed). Hence, there are no strings attached to its power.
From this notion of an agreement comes the idea of a social
contract—a legal arrangement among the governed to submit equally to a common
authority (everyone surrenders all of his or her power to the outside party of
the sovereign). It’s almost impossible to overestimate the importance of this
concept in modern politics, for it introduces a number of ideas absolutely
fundamental to our modern political arguments. The first is that the individual
has an identity and certain rights independent of the state. He may trade these
rights for the security a state offers, but there are some he can never forfeit
(if the state, for example, fails to provide such security or seeks to take his
life, the contract is void and the obligation to obey the sovereign
disappears). Such a view of individual rights is completely foreign to the Old
Order, where the individual has no existence outside the state (indeed the
state provides the individual his identity, his most fundamental sense of who
he is)—whatever rights he enjoys (if he has any at all) are conferred by the
state or by communal traditions, not by his existence as an independent human
being—and he certainly has no authority to challenge the state in the name of
certain rights he enjoys just because he’s a human being.
The second vital principle this idea of the social contract puts
on the table is the enormously important modern notion that the state exists by
the consent of the governed, indeed, that the very legitimacy of the state
requires such consent (hence, we tend to see a state as illegitimate if there’s
no evidence of consent). Hobbes is not arguing that such a social contract is
necessarily a historical event. He’s arguing that if you think about political
issues, your reason will persuade you that such a concept is the rational way
to proceed—we should accept the legitimacy of the state he is proposing because
it’s rational to suppose that, if we were in a state of nature, we would want
to come out of it on the terms Hobbes is outlining.
A third important concept here is the sense of equality under the
law—all citizens, as equal partners to the contract, are equally bound to obey
the sovereign. There is not one law for the rich or the righteous and another
law for the poor or the profane. Inherited rank or one’s family connections or
one’s economic power confer no special privileges, no release from one’s
obligation to obey just like everyone else.
And, most importantly, Hobbes’ system permits and promotes a new
kind of freedom. Because in the Hobbesian state our
only duty is to obey the law, we have freedom to do whatever the law does not
forbid. Hence, where the law is silent, we acquire the freedom to do what we
like, without the restrictions of public opinion or competing religious or
community traditions. Such personal freedom is different from the traditional
notions of freedom as the liberty of a state to govern itself. Under the Old
Order a state might well be free in the latter sense (i.e., free to govern
itself), yet grant its citizens very little personal liberty—in fact, given the
importance of public opinion and uncontested religious traditions in small
communities, for the most part there was relatively little personal freedom for
anyone, rich or poor, simply because their behaviour
was always closely regulated by social forces and moral codes operating all the
time around them, even in their own lives at home.
Hobbes believes that this new liberty, what has come to be called
Negative Liberty, will enable people to concentrate on what they really want to
do, which is to make money and to construct their own secure middle-class lives
in isolation from and competition with each other. If the state gives them a
chance to channel their natural greed and competitiveness into profitable
activity, they will be peaceful and law abiding, and the wealth they generate
will keep the state strong. We don’t have to try to make people good or
happy—we simply have to keep them from killing each other over religious
questions and let them follow their desires as competitive and acquisitive
individuals to make money for themselves. It’s a system tailor-made for the
emerging free-market capitalism of the time. In effect, Hobbes’ theory is
predicated on his assumption that people would rather make money and live
comfortably than continue to fight each other over religion.
Hobbes’ state thus consists of two worlds: the public sphere in
which the sovereign’s control is all-powerful and the citizens’ duty requires
obedience to the law (because that’s what they’ve agreed to) and a private
sphere in which the citizen is free of obligation to anyone. This concept of
Negative Liberty—personal freedom to do whatever we want in our private
space—is at the centre of what we call Liberalism. We can and do argue all the
time about how big or small this sphere of personal freedom should be (at the
moment we seem to be reducing it in the name of national security), but we all
see it as essential to our way of life and, in fact, devote a great deal of our
lives to creating and protecting a private space for ourselves, where we can
live without having to deal with annoying things like other people or the government.
Most of you, for example, place a very high value on having your own private
space and are looking forward to constructing your own private life where you
do not have to answer to any outside authority. This notion, which we
take for granted, is a modern idea, born in Hobbes’ model of the state.
Another vital new principle Hobbes’ liberal vision introduces is
the legal nature of political obligations. Whereas, in the Old Order political
power and obedience were closely linked to particular people, families, and
inherited relationships and old traditions, in Hobbes’ vision, power and
obedience are linked only to the legally established office rather than the
person. We obey the Nanaimo City Council’s rules not because of the people who
sit around the Council table or because of old traditions, but because of the
positions they occupy, which are established and backed up and can be changed
by the authority of the Sovereign. Once Gary Korpan
ceases to be mayor of Nanaimo, he loses all his public authority, which rests
with the position, not with the person. Political authority thus is stripped of
its traditional dynastic basis: I have no obligation to obey anyone just
because of who he or she might be, since my legal obligations extend only to
positions of authority established and backed up by the sovereign’s power, not
to the people who occupy them.
I’ve spent some time on Hobbes because he, in effect, sets down
the blueprint for modern liberal political thinking, and, even if he was
frequently vilified for his hostility to traditions and religion, the thinkers
who come after him are very much responding, in various ways, to what he
proposed (for a more detailed look at Hobbes, you might like to consult this
link—Hobbes).
JOHN LOCKE
John Locke, for example, writing about half a century after
Hobbes, adopts his vision of the liberal state in all its most important basic
principles. He does, however, make some important and influential adjustments
by ameliorating Hobbes’ very reductive vision of human nature and by seeking to
deal with what many perceived as the most dangerous feature of Hobbes’ vision
of the political state, the excessive power in the hands of the sovereign.
Where Hobbes is seeking, at all costs, to limit the ability of citizens to
fight each other (especially over religious questions), Locke is more concerned
to protect citizens against the tyranny of the government (the difference may
reflect the different political climates—by Locke’s time the fear of and
experience with civil wars in the name of religion had faded considerably).
Hence, for Locke, when individuals living in a state of nature
enter into a social contract to form the society, they do not surrender all
their rights and submit themselves unconditionally to the law of the sovereign.
They retain certain key entitlements (rights) which act as permanent limits to
the control the government can exert over them. Thus, there is still a contract
and the consent of the governed and the rule of law, but the contract is more
complicated. Negative liberty, with Locke, has some built-in guarantees, and
these guarantees are enshrined in the document which establishes the social
contract, namely, the constitution.
The most famous examples of what Locke is proposing are the
documents his ideas did so much to shape, the Declaration of Independence and
the American Constitution. The latter document enables a citizen to do
something which in Hobbes’ state is not possible (except when the state comes
for one’s life)—to challenge the government’s authority to enact and enforce a
particular law and thus to limit that citizen’s ability to do as she likes
(like carrying guns, or expressing her opinions, or organizing a meeting of
fellow citizens, or worshipping at a church of her choice, and so on). And, as
we witness all the time, it gives the law courts the enormously important task
of sorting out just what certain constitutional rights mean in relation to particular
pieces of legislation. In a state where citizens have constitutional rights,
their private space is protected against government interference much more
clearly than in a state where such rights do not exist. In this connection, it’s
interesting to note that the United Kingdom, the original home of liberal
theory, has no constitution—it follows Hobbes’ idea that total authority rests
with the sovereign—hence there is no judicial appeal against the laws passed by
parliament, as there is in the United States and now in Canada.
Before leaving these two enormously important liberal thinkers, it’s
important to make one further point. Neither of them is particularly interested
in whether the citizens are happy in their personal lives in a political system
that encourages personal freedom and competition at the expense of communal
traditions (the “pursuit of happiness” is a wonderfully ambiguous phrase). Nor
are they concerned with the moral quality of citizens’ lives. What matters is
obedience to the law, not adherence to any particular moral code or, indeed,
any moral code at all. Finally, neither of them is particularly concerned with
equality—other than the important idea of equality under the law. The
Liberalism of Hobbes and Locke is designed to promote individual economic
activity in a spirit of competition, within the boundaries established by laws
binding on everyone, an arrangement that virtually guarantees that some citizens
will be very much richer than others and will be free to spend their money as
they see fit and that some citizens will fail in their economic activities.
JEAN JACQUES ROUSSEAU
The most powerful, passionate, and paradoxical response to Hobbes
came about one hundred years after he published his massive masterpiece, when
Jean Jacques Rousseau, a citizen of Geneva in Switzerland, wrote his political
discourses—especially the Second Discourse (On Inequality) and his Third
Discourse (The Social Contract). In these works, Rousseau lays the
initial ground work for the West’s most historically important alternative to
the liberal model defined by Hobbes and Locke.
Rousseau begins by adopting Hobbes’ basic metaphor: human beings
originally existed in a state of nature; this ended with a social contract
which established civil society. But he drastically alters the emphasis. For
Rousseau, man in a state of nature was perfectly happy, independent, free, and
self-sufficient (a “noble savage”). The social contract was a disaster because,
in setting up society, human beings inevitably introduced inequality—some
people ended up with more property or more esteem than others, and this brought
about all human unhappiness and oppression, which arise, most importantly, not
merely from material differences but also from psychological states. Inequality
makes people feel unhappy, because they cannot help comparing themselves with
others who have more goods, more talent, or more honours.
And psychological distress of this kind is, for Rousseau, a form of oppression.
For a more detailed discussion of this aspect of Rousseau’s thinking, you might
want to explore this link: Rousseau.
Rousseau has three major objections to what Hobbes and Locke are
proposing. First, Rousseau argues that in such a modern liberal state, human
beings will end up trading the complete freedom they enjoyed in a state of
nature for a small and insufficient fraction of freedom given by the state (How
can human beings be truly free when they have to obey the sovereign?). Second,
as mentioned above, he sees in the inequality produced by liberal competition a
source of material and psychological oppression (something Hobbes and Locke do
not concern themselves with). Rousseau is particularly sensitive to how people
who have a certain political freedom can become economic slaves to the market
place and psychological slaves to the images of the materially good life. And
third, he objects strongly to the reductive view of human beings basic to
Hobbes’ theory. If human life is to be worth anything, Rousseau argues, a person
has to have a moral worth as an independent individual capable of making rational
decisions about his own life for moral reasons, rather than operating merely as
an economic agent whose only duty is to obey the sovereign’s law without question.
Rousseau realizes that there’s no going back to a State of Nature,
no matter how utopian that existence may have been. Human beings now have to
live in society, among other human beings. So the challenge to the political
theorist is to find a way to organize a state in which human beings are as free
as they were in a state of nature (or feel no loss of freedom by existing in
society) and in which they feel that they are fully equal, without any psychologically
crippling sense that they are better or worse than anyone else in any way. And
finally, the political arrangements should encourage the full moral development
of the individual citizen as a self-governing, independent, rational moral
being. What he’s demanding, of course, is a very tall order—a utopian arrangement
in which the individual lives in civil society without losing any sense of
independence and freedom and without any feelings of psychological inadequacy
or inferiority.
His answer is complex, and I have time here (again) to provide
only a very rough preliminary sketch of his argument (in The Social
Contract). To begin with, Rousseau rejects any form of government other
than a majoritarian democracy in which all citizens
participate equally at all times in the decision making (hence the state must
be relatively small). If the citizens are educated enough to see the
reasonableness of this arrangement (a very important condition), they will come
to understand that in following the decisions of the majority of all the
citizens (as these decisions emerge from an assembly of all citizens) they will
be following the General Will of the state, which will always be right (provided,
as mentioned, the citizens have all been educated in the appropriate way). A
person who disagrees with the General Will in any particular decision will
understand that the mistake belongs to her and not the community. Such a communitarian
arrangement, Rousseau argues, must be extremely careful not to create a complex
bureaucracy of government which will inevitably arrogate power to itself and sabotage the legitimacy of the state, which rests
on the fact that all its members are equally important in the decision making.
Rousseau argues that an arrangement like this would enable people to obey the
state without any sense of a loss of freedom, because they would be following
what their reason told them was the right thing to do, and self-imposed rules
do not register as a loss of freedom. In effect, they would be obeying
themselves (“You should obey the state because you are the state”).
In addition, Rousseau stresses the need for the citizens to engage
in trades which will, as much as possible, make them self-sufficient and which
will not require very much social interaction, dependence on others, or
economic competition (one way of dealing with the psychological distress caused
by comparing people with oneself is to interact with others as little as
possible). In this way, the citizen will remain independent and will retain
full control over his own life. An educated awareness of the dangers of certain
cultural productions (plays, books, music) will inhibit the development of
images of life which threaten the citizen’s satisfaction with what he has at
present and which make him want what he cannot have. Under such conditions, he
will be reasonable enough to understand that he should limit his material wants
and resist the lure of the capitalist market place, which will always be seeking
to persuade him to acquire unnecessary goods, the possession of which will set
him apart from his fellow citizens and promote feelings of inequality and
dissatisfaction.
It’s important to notice a couple of things about Rousseau’s proposal.
First, he’s emphatic about how important it is that people have to be educated
into understanding an arrangement like this. Where Hobbes and Locke settle for
people as they are, warts and all, and seek to channel their natural vices into
useful economic activity, Rousseau wants people to be better than they
typically are, to develop more fully as happy, independent, free, rational
moralists, and they will have to be educated to do that if his system is to
work. But Rousseau is not claiming that this can happen with people as they are
now, except perhaps under very unusual circumstances in very specific places
(e.g., in Corsica). Second, Rousseau is extremely pessimistic about a state
like the one he’s proposing ever being successfully implemented or, if it is,
lasting very long. So he has very little to offer by way of a practical program
of action to achieve such a political ideal.
The best examples of some of the main features of what Rousseau is
proposing are offered by certain forms of communal living (the Israeli kibbutz,
for example), where a relatively small community governs itself with the equal
participation of all and where there is much less emphasis on competitive economic
activity to promote the accumulation of personal goods to decorate a private
space. There are many tributes to the psychological and economic benefits of
such an arrangement (and no shortage of volunteers who prefer these arrangements
to normal liberal society). It may well be the case that many of us would be
much happier and productive in such a state than in what we have available
around us. It is, however, difficult to find successful large-scale examples of
such communitarian political structures.
Rousseau’s vision has been immensely influential, especially among
those who don’t like the spirit of economic competition at the heart of
traditional liberalism and who think that a political system has some responsibility
for the personal happiness and the moral stature of its citizens—and, most
importantly, among those who believe that there is an important priority that
liberalism not only ignores but subverts, namely equality.
For it’s clear that in the competitive climate promoted by Hobbesian liberalism, there will be a lot of economic
losers (as in any competition). What obligation does the state have to those
people? Well, according to the models proposed by Hobbes and Locke, not very
much. If people squander their opportunities, that’s their problem. If they are
unhappy about the fact that some people are much better off and can afford many
more things, well, tough luck. They had their chances, just like everyone else,
and if they don’t make it, well, that means they haven’t got it.
For all its reservations, Rousseau’s writing offers those who
object to such a Liberal view an alluring vision of a society in which people
have been re-educated into a new way of dealing with each other in a spirit of
equal and free communal cooperation in a political system stressing equality.
For that reason Rousseau is often accused, fairly or unfairly, of being the
godfather of all sorts of tyrannical experiments which seek to re-educate
citizens by force into some new communal utopia (in Camille Paglia’s
characteristically pumped-up prose “All roads from Rousseau lead to
totalitarianism”).
[Parenthetically, it’s interesting to note that Canadians have always
valued equality much more than Americans have, especially in our educational,
medical, and welfare systems—thanks largely to the influence in Canada of
socialist political parties, some of whom derive their original inspiration
from Rousseau. That priority is under considerable attack at the moment, of
course, as there is increasing pressure to hand these systems, or significant
parts of them, over to the market place, to free trade. It will be interesting
to see just how far we are prepared to go to protect this tradition—which, of
course, imposes important limitations on some people’s freedom]
KARL MARX
But the most penetrating, influential, and long-lasting challenge
to the liberal tradition established by Hobbes and Locke (and energetically
defended by John Stuart Mill) came in the mid-nineteenth century from Karl
Marx, who directed his formidable intellectual powers into a thoroughgoing
critique of liberal capitalism as it had developed on the basis of the political
models advocated by those earlier thinkers.
Marx admired many things about liberal capitalism, especially its
ability to generate fabulous wealth and to sweep ancient traditions out of the
way. But Marx was genuinely horrified by the staggering inequalities created by
that system. When he looked around him he saw increasing numbers of people who
in theory enjoyed so-called liberal freedoms (their constitutional right to
free speech and so on) but who were, in fact, abject slaves to an economic
system which barely enabled them to survive. Was this really freedom? What use
were the celebrated liberal freedoms if a majority of the citizens, including
children, had no economic freedom and were forced into a short and brutal life
of exploitation to make the fabulously rich factory owners even richer?
This response led Marx to a long and detailed study of capitalism.
Again, this is a complex topic, but Marx makes a very strong case that
free-market capitalism is, over time, an extremely destructive enterprise,
because the conditions for free competition inevitably make fewer and fewer
people richer and richer and leave more and more people out of work or living
desperately near subsistence level. Over time, Marx argues, these conditions
will encourage in those at the bottom a collective awareness of their common
plight (in his words they will develop a “class consciousness”) and, with a new
understanding of the reasons for their distress, they will revolt against their
capitalist owners, take over the means of production, and distribute the
enormous wealth generated by the productive forces of capitalism more justly.
Hence, the inherent problems of capitalism will lead to a new political
structure, Communism, in which everyone owns the means of production and
benefits equally from the wealth generated. People will be free of economic
wants and will thus be able to take charge of their lives in a spirit of free
cooperation, without the need for one citizen to oppress another. They
will obey the state because, once again, they are the state. Politics
will then cease to be a complicated affair, because all citizens will happily
give what they can and take what they need (a communal utopian ideal).
This process, according to Marx, is historically inevitable, but
it requires (as in Rousseau) the development of a new understanding in people
about the nature of society and their own role within it. Communism cannot be
imposed arbitrarily; it will emerge inevitably as the desperate conditions
inevitably created by liberal capitalism force more and more people to
understand the nature of the problem and the obvious need to find and answer to it through cooperative political efforts.
Liberal Capitalism, Marx argues, will take steps to slow this process
down (by consolidating, automation, going off-shore, marketing new products,
and so on), but this will simply postpone the moment when the increasing
numbers of its victims rise in rebellion and the new communal spirit begins to
emerge, fuelled by a demand for economic justice.
Marx’s analysis of liberal capitalism is extraordinarily acute. He
may very well have been wrong about the time line, and he almost certainly
underestimated the ability of capitalism to adjust in order to defuse the revolutionary
potential of those injured by the system, but his analysis about the inevitably
dislocating and self-destructive effects of free-market capitalism is still a
very prescient way of understanding just the sort of social disruptions we are
so depressingly familiar with (mill closures, company takeovers with massive
lay-offs, corporate scandals on the stock market, jobs moving overseas, automation,
boom-and-bust economic cycles, increasing concentration of social and economic
power in fewer and fewer hands, so on). Those who wish to explore this topic in
more detail might consult the following link: Marx.
Marx provides both theoretical coherence and a practical program
of action for those who wish to offer some political alternative to the liberal
models of Hobbes and Locke. Under that influence, most Western countries have
developed a strong and influential socialist tradition, whose major aim is to
pressure society to recognize the importance of equality in the face of the
growing gap between rich and poor, which Marx sees as the inevitable result of
traditional liberalism. And this influence has led most capitalist countries to
modify the doctrines of free-market capitalism significantly by introducing
important measures to ameliorate the inequalities of free competition, many of
them expressly recommended by Marx—free public education, unions, federal control
of banking and transportation, welfare assistance, income tax, and so on. It’s
clear that such measures have been adopted not because liberal capitalists
thought they were good in themselves (they are all limitations on personal
freedom) but rather because they were necessary to defuse the revolutionary
potential in the working classes. And in certain areas, especially environmental
issues, increasing numbers of people have become aware of the importance of
more cooperation at the expense of liberty (e.g., closing the cod fishery,
imposing environmental standards for industry, banning whaling, restricting oil
drilling, and so on).
With the fall of the Soviet Union, many people are tempted to
write Communism off as a viable political system (overlooking the fact that the
Soviet Union was hardly based on genuine Marxist principles). Whatever the
truth of that claim or not, Marx’s analysis of liberal capitalism, especially
his insistence on the necessarily dislocating effects of the inequalities associated
with that system, are still very hard to answer. He may have misjudged the
march of history and the extent to which human beings are capable of developing
class consciousness in the way he describes (in that sense he may have been
wrong about the viability of Communism as a political system), but capitalism
still has to find an entirely satisfactory answer to his analysis of its
built-in deficiencies.
A FINAL COMMENT
For all their significant differences, the thinkers very quickly
reviewed above had one thing in common: they believed that modern political
thinking must be based on reason, on a rational analysis of human nature and of
the conditions necessary for freedom and justice, in states maintained by the
consent of the governed. Hence, they would almost all share a certain despair
and wonder at the extent to which modern politics has in some places been dominated
by irrationality, by, for example, the success of charismatic tyrants who
justify their activities by the cult of personality or by racial-ethnic-nationalistic
metaphors or by a return to theocracy, the rule of the clerisy in the name of a
traditional religion (like Islamic fundamentalism).
Dealing with such states creates real problems for Liberals and
Communists alike, because they rest on principles foreign to the entire modern
Western tradition and hence are often frustratingly incomprehensible to
Westerners (who, for example, can have great trouble recognizing the genuine
popularity of charismatic, brutal tyrants or oppressive religious ruling
councils). It’s very hard for us to accept that some people may not want
democracy, do not place a particularly high value on personal liberty to do as
they wish, and are not concerned about the consent of the governed or citizens’
rights in the way that our models of the state require.
In the West, the Hobbes-Locke formulation of liberal political
order is very much alive and in the ascendant, as the hard-won adjustments to
that brought about by a socialism inspired by Marx are, bit by bit, being shredded
by the need to keep capitalism dynamic (e.g., the erosion of the power of the unions,
the move to privatize medical services, the retreat of government from various
public services, the rising costs of post-secondary education, and so on) and
by the growing power of giant corporations. At the same time, however, the
threats posed by terrorism are leading many Western governments to introduce
significant limitations on personal liberty in the name of national security.
It’s also clear that the political and economic success of Western
liberalism is helping to increase the already alarming gap between rich and
poor throughout the world, in precisely the way Marx predicted. There is no
shortage of dire warnings about the urgent need to address this issue with
something more than World Trade Organization meetings and World Bank loans. But
any intelligent and effective steps for more global justice may well require a
significant re-evaluation of the very principles on which the success of that
liberalism depends. But that’s a matter for another time.
[Back
to johnstonia Home Page]
Page loads on johnstonia web files
View
Stats