John Black, Malaspina University College, February 1997
It seems to me, first of all, that there are two perspectives from which we ought to judge arguments supporting the contention that liberal learning should be granted at least equal, if not greater, emphasis in our post- secondary system. Let me oversimplify outrageously by calling them the "rational" and "rhetorical" perspectives. What I want to suggest is that, in so far as these arguments are to serve in a campaign, of a sort, for the preservation of the liberal arts, it is important that they satisfy two related but different sets of criteria. They must be rationally sound, on the one hand, but also, on the other, rhetorically effective at convincing those who tend to the opposite view. It is primarily from the second perspective that I am prone to impatience with many educators who argue for the out-and-out superiority of liberal education over vocational training, on the grounds that their objectives are fundamentally distinct, and that those of the academy are infinitely preferable to those of the workshop. Yet arguments of this nature are not immune from rational criticism also.
I think I can agree that in some rather general sense the flourishing of the whole person is probably more important than the development of advanced welding skills. However, this judgment has an air of the Platonic about it, since it ignores a host of contextual factors relevant to the appropriateness of a particular form of learning for a particular individual at a particular point in that person's life. It is not elitist to admit that some people are ill- equipped to reap the full benefits of liberal education, and given the sorts of socio-economic pressures which drive many to enter the post-secondary system as students, it strikes me as supercilious, if not socially pernicious, to assert that they would be better served by Humanities 130 than by Office Administration 100. A further assumption of this view is that the nominal objective - human flourishing - is in fact achieved by liberal education but not by career training. While I have no doubts about the positive claim here, I think the negative one is contentious in the light of recent advances in vocational pedagogy. [1]
In any case, arguments which preach the unequivocal superiority of liberal education over career training are not likely to engineer assent among faculty and administrators of an applied bent, whatever their intrinsic strength. And it is not necessary to employ such arguments in order to support the conclusion at hand, that liberal education opportunities should be maintained and enhanced in the BC system. As Rhoda Friedrichs [2] has pointed out, one of the important arguments in favour of liberal education, one which she attributes to BC Premier Glen Clark, accepts the legitimacy of career-related objectives in education, and stresses the very great extent to which liberal education enhances employability. Before examining this argument in more detail, however, I want first to comment on Bob Nichols' [3] contrary suggestion that education is definitionally distinguished from training by the fact that it cannot be said to have any instrumental purpose at all.
I think the main difference between Nichols and myself on this issue can be brought out as follows: suppose that he is right when he claims that education is, by definition, an end-in-itself which cannot be justified by any further end. [4] Presumably, then, Glen Clark's argument is not one in favour of liberal education, but one in favour of what we should have to call "liberal training." This reveals, however, why Nichols' definitional claims about education are difficult to sustain, for it would not be disastrous for my courses in Philosophy or Liberal Studies, say, either that they happen to enhance the employment skills and prospects of my students or that I believe that the fact that they do so is part of the justification for offering them. The intrinsic value of the learning involved would not be tainted in any way by its having also an instrumental value, or by its being thought to have it. [5]
Because of this, and because what liberal education is is defined more reasonably by what liberal educators do than by its real or intended effects, we should not shun the suggestion that liberal education can be supported by reference to its success in the development of general employability skills.
Useem's conclusions are based upon a combination of objective and subjective factors. Working on college graduates of the late eighties, employed in 1989 in the American corporate sector, he compares the salaries, rank, promotion rates and so on of graduates with a variety of degrees. He also reports on the attitudes of top-level managers towards the educational credentials of their employees. The study is too detailed, and the conclusions too intricate, for a full treatment here, but the overall message is that those who succeed best in the corporate sector are those who combine in their educational backgrounds both business studies, or some similar professional program, and the liberal arts. Such graduates far outrank engineers, for example, in their ability to gain promotion in management.
Allen's discussion investigates the local employment economy in BC from more or less the same point of view, except that he is concerned specifically to compare degree graduates with those who have taken instead some form of vocational or career diploma. The study concerns the employment fates of 1990 graduates, as this is the latest year for which StatsCan and other relevant data are available. Again the conclusions are multifarious, but the overall message is a clear vote of confidence in favour of degrees. An important part of Allen's article is devoted to a debunking of the (rather ironically named) Training for What? report prepared for the BC Labour Force Development Board. He shows convincingly that that report based its conclusions in favour of increased emphasis on career programs not on actual employment outcomes, but instead on a theoretical job-forecasting model which has little empirical validity. One can only speculate about whether Glen Clark's remarks supporting liberal education betoken a change of heart, at the government level, occasioned by Allen's study. It seems clear, however, that the provincial hegemony of the Training for What? model is at last on the wane.
These empirical studies are perhaps not entirely immune to criticism themselves. Retrospective studies obviously have the feature that they are no more current than the last year for which data is now available, and in the present cases that year occurred seven years ago. In planning for the future, it might be argued, only a theoretical model which incorporates the best guesses as to changes in the employment market will be sufficient.
Nevertheless, aside from the fact that according to Allen Training for What? uses an arbitrary model, the likelihood is that we can place appreciable weight on the retrospective data favouring liberal education. This is because such education has always emphasized not job-specific skills, which might become obsolete as the world of work changes, but the transferable abilities (to think, solve problems, communicate, learn to learn, work in teams etc.) identified by the Conference Board of Canada [8] as generic employability skills. It is precisely the flexibility engendered by these skills, it is plausible to argue, which will enable today's graduates to negotiate tomorrow's employment uncertainties.
It's too early yet, of course, to predict the future career trajectories of these graduates, but I feel pretty confident that their lives will corroborate the findings of Useem and Allen, and show that it makes sense to extrapolate from those findings into the next century. Those who have chosen to follow a liberal education with specific career training, in professional school for example, will discover that they have created for themselves the best of both worlds. They will demonstrate that "Education vs. Training" is a false dilemma not only theoretically, but also practically, since their education will have included training in both general and specific skills.
These observations, and the empirical studies I mentioned earlier, suggest models for curriculum development at the new university colleges, and for any others which are created in the future. One model involves combining four-year degrees focusing on a wide range of general skills, in the traditional liberal arts mould, with one-year post-graduate diplomas to enable students to set their first feet in the workplace door. Another would include the professional training as a minor in a liberal arts major. These models exist in BC universities - in teacher education, for example - but the university colleges are better positioned to implement them than the universities since, drawing upon the resources of their existing vocational and career programs, they can offer a much wider range of training on the professional end.
Unfortunately, models which try to combine the advantages of what have traditionally been distinguished as education and training have not received much attention at Malaspina, nor, I think, at the other university colleges. In Nanaimo at any rate, all recent efforts in degree development have gone into traditional disciplinary majors similar to those available at the universities. As a philosopher, I am partly pleased by the fact that liberal education (though with the exception of the Liberal Studies program perhaps not of a kind sufficiently interdisciplinary for my own tastes) is receiving emphasis in the struggle between education and training. The other part of me regrets our inability to transcend this conceptual dichotomy and to open our thinking to models of undergraduate education which combine the advantages of both of its poles. Nevertheless, if it is only possible to opt for one of the poles, Useem and Allen, along with my own experience, have convinced me that liberal education is by far the better.
2. Rhoda L. Friedrichs: "What Do We Need to Know?: Liberal Education and the Free Society," Discourse 2:1 (Fall 1996), p. 16.
3. Robert Nichols: "The Value of Education and Training," Discourse 2:1 (Fall 1996), p. 13.
4. For brevity of expression, I am adopting here a terminology which, like Nichols', ignores Aristotle's crucial distinction between productive and constitutive means-ends relationships. When Nichols denies that education is instrumentally useful, he is denying that there is any productive end, any distinct state-of-affairs which it produces and which justifies it as a practice. I do not think he would wish to deny that it is possible to talk of education as having a constitutive end, a state-of-affairs which constitutes being educated and which can be judged to be valuable in itself. My references to "human flourishing" gesture towards the characterization of such a constitutive end, and are thoroughly Aristotelian in spirit. Thus it would be possible to agree with Nichols that education is not to be justified instrumentally without being committed to his arguably incautious claim that the essence of education is its "groundlessness" or "pointlessness" (ibid.).
5. This is an oversimplification. What I take to be Nichols' point here is salutary in so far as it alerts liberal educators to the danger of shifting emphasis, within their curricula and pedagogies, away from humanistic objectives and towards the development of skills associated with a limited conception of employment. Too formulaic an approach, for example, to outcomes-based instruction could overlook the self-questioning aspects of liberal education, and this would be a bad thing. However, the temptation can be resisted and, furthermore, these aspects themselves speak to an important component of employability skills as I see them.
6. Michael Useem: Liberal Education and the Corporation: The Hiring and Advancement of College Graduates, New York, Aldine de Gruyter, 1990.
7. Robert Allen: "The Economic Benefits of Post-Secondary Training and Education in BC: March 1996," in UBC Reports 42:9, May 2 1996.
8. The Conference Board of Canada: Employability Skills Profile, 1993.